Benjamin Aw
Add updated pkl file v3
6fa4bc9
{
"paper_id": "E89-1002",
"header": {
"generated_with": "S2ORC 1.0.0",
"date_generated": "2023-01-19T10:34:16.926013Z"
},
"title": "PARSING AND DERIVATIONAL EQUIVALENCE*",
"authors": [
{
"first": "Mark",
"middle": [],
"last": "Hepple",
"suffix": "",
"affiliation": {},
"email": ""
},
{
"first": "Glyn",
"middle": [],
"last": "Morrill",
"suffix": "",
"affiliation": {},
"email": ""
}
],
"year": "",
"venue": null,
"identifiers": {},
"abstract": "It is a tacit assumption of much linguistic inquiry that all distinct derivations of a string should assign distinct meanings. But despite the tidiness of such derivational uniqueness, there seems to be no a priori reason to assume that a gramma r must have this property. If a grammar exhibits derivational equivalence, whereby distinct derivations of a string assign the same meanings, naive exhaustive search for all derivations will be redundant, and quite possibly intractable. In this paper we show how notions of derivation-reduction and normal form can be used to avoid unnecessary work while parsing with grammars exhibiting derivational equivalence. With grammar regarded as analogous to logic, derivations are proofs; what we are advocating is proof-reduction, and normal form proof; the invocation of these logical techniques adds a further paragraph to the story of parsing-as-deduction.",
"pdf_parse": {
"paper_id": "E89-1002",
"_pdf_hash": "",
"abstract": [
{
"text": "It is a tacit assumption of much linguistic inquiry that all distinct derivations of a string should assign distinct meanings. But despite the tidiness of such derivational uniqueness, there seems to be no a priori reason to assume that a gramma r must have this property. If a grammar exhibits derivational equivalence, whereby distinct derivations of a string assign the same meanings, naive exhaustive search for all derivations will be redundant, and quite possibly intractable. In this paper we show how notions of derivation-reduction and normal form can be used to avoid unnecessary work while parsing with grammars exhibiting derivational equivalence. With grammar regarded as analogous to logic, derivations are proofs; what we are advocating is proof-reduction, and normal form proof; the invocation of these logical techniques adds a further paragraph to the story of parsing-as-deduction.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Abstract",
"sec_num": null
}
],
"body_text": [
{
"text": "The phenomenon of derivational equivalence is most evident in work on generalised categorial grammars, where it has been referred to as ~spurious ambiguity'. It has been argued that the capacity to assign left-branching, and therefore incrementally interpretable, analyses makes these grammars of particular psychological interest. We will illustrate our methodology by reference to generalised categorial grammars using a combinatory logic (as opposed to say, lambda-calculus) semantics. In particular we consider combinatory (categorial) grammars with rules and generalised rules *We thank Mike Reape for criticism and suggestions in relation to this material, and Inge Bethke and Henk Zeevat for reading a late draft. All errors are our own. The work was carried out by the alphabetically first author under ESRC Postgraduate Award C00428722003 and by the second under ESRC Postgraduate Award C00428522008 and an SERC Postdoctoral Fellowship in IT.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Introduction",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "of the kind of Steedman (1987) , and with metarules (Morri~ 19ss) .",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 15,
"end": 30,
"text": "Steedman (1987)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF11"
},
{
"start": 52,
"end": 65,
"text": "(Morri~ 19ss)",
"ref_id": null
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Introduction",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Although the problem of derivational equivalence is most apparent in generalised categorial grammars, the problem is likely to recur in many grammars characterising a full complement of constructions. For example, suppose that a grammar is capable of characterising right extraposition of an object's adjunct to clause-final position. Then sentences such as Joha met a man yesterday who swims will be generated. But it is probable that the same grammar will assign Joha met a maa who swims a right extraposition derivation in which the relative clause happens to occupy its normal position in the string; the normal and right extraposition derivations generate the same strings with the same meanings, so there is derivational equivalence. Note that a single equivalence of this kind in a grammar undermines a methodological assumption of derivational uniqueness.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Introduction",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Combinatory logic (CL; Curry and Feys, 1958; Curry, Hindley and Seldin, 1972; Hindley and Seldin, 1986) refers to systems which are applicative, like the lambda-calculi, but which formalise functional abstraction through a small number of basic 'combinators', rather than through a variable-binding operator like A. We will define a typed combinatory logic. Assume a set of basic types, say e and t. Then the set of types is defined as follows:",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 23,
"end": 44,
"text": "Curry and Feys, 1958;",
"ref_id": "BIBREF1"
},
{
"start": 45,
"end": 77,
"text": "Curry, Hindley and Seldin, 1972;",
"ref_id": "BIBREF1"
},
{
"start": 78,
"end": 103,
"text": "Hindley and Seldin, 1986)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF4"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(1) a. If A is a basic type then A is a type b. If A and B are types then A-*B is a type A convention of right-associativity will be used for types, so that e.g. (e--,t)-*(e--,t) may be writ-ten (e---*t)--*e--,t. There is a set of constants (say, John', walks', ...) , and a mapping from the set of constants into the set of types. In addition there are the combinators in (2); their lambda-analogues are shown in parentheses.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 241,
"end": 266,
"text": "(say, John', walks', ...)",
"ref_id": null
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(2) IA-.., A",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "B(B-~ C)-* (A--~B)-*A-*C C (A-* B--~C)-~ B--* A--~C W(A--* A-*B)-*A--*B (~x[x]) (~x~y~,.[x(y--)}) (~x~y~,.[(x,)y]) (AxAy[(xy)y])",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The set of CL-terms is defined thus:",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(3) a. If M is a constant or combinator of type A then M is a CL-term of type A b. If M is a CL-term of type B---~A and N is a CLterm of type B then (MN) is a CL-term of type A.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The interpretation of a term built by (3b) is given by the functional application of the interpretation of the left-hand sub-term to that of the righthand one. We will assume a convention of leftassociation for application. Some examples of CLterms are as follows, where the types are written below each component term: Other basic combinators can be used in a CL, for example S, which corresponds to Ax~yAz[(xz)(yz)]. Our CL definition is (extensionally) equivalent to the ALcalculus, i.e. the lambda-calculus without vacuous abstraction (terms of the form AxM where x does not occur in M). There is a combinator K (AxAy[x]) which would introduce vacuous abstraction, and the CL with S and K is (extensionally) equivalent to the AK-calculus, i.e. the full lambdacalculus.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "A combinatory grammar (CG) can be defined in a largely analogous manner. Assume a set of basic categories, say S, NP, ... Then the set of categories is defined as follows:",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(5) a. If X is a basic category then X is a category b. If X and Y are categories then X/Y and X\\Y are categories A convention of left-associativity will be used for categories, so that e.g. (S\\NP)\\(S\\NP) may be written S\\NP\\(S\\NP). There is a set of words, and a lexical association of words with categories. There is a set of rules with combinators, minimally:",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(6) a. Forward Application (>) f: X/Y+Y=~X (wherefxy=xy) b. Backward Application (<) b: Y+X\\Y ::~ X (wherebyx=xy)",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The set of CG-terms is defined thus: The interpretation of a term built by (Tb) is given by the functional application of the combinator to the sub-term interpretations in left-to-right order.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "A verb phrase containing an auxiliary can be derived as in (8) (throughout, VP abbreviates S\\NP). The meaning assigned is given by (ga), which is equal to (91)).",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Combinatory Logic and Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "will see John",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "(8)",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "VP/VP VP/NP NP .> VP ) VP (9) a. (f will' (f see' John')) b. will' (see' John')",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "(8)",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Suppose the grammar is augmented with a rule of functional composition (10), as is claimed to be appropriate for analysis of extraction and coordination (Ades and Steedman, 1982; Steedman, 1985) . Then for example, the right hand conjunct in (lla) can be analysed as shown in (llb). (12) (f (B will' see') John') However the grammar now exhibits derivational equivalence, with different derivations assigning the same meaning.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 153,
"end": 178,
"text": "(Ades and Steedman, 1982;",
"ref_id": "BIBREF0"
},
{
"start": 179,
"end": 194,
"text": "Steedman, 1985)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF10"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "(8)",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "In general a sequence A1/A2 +A2/A3 9.A3/A4 9.\"'9\"An can be analysed aS AI with the same meaning by combining any pair of adjacent elements at each step. Thus there are a number of equivalent derivations equal to the number of n-leaf binary trees; this is given by the Catalan series, which is such that Catalan(n) > 2 '~-2. As well as it being inefficient to search through derivations which are equivalent, the exponential figure signifies computational intractability.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "(8)",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Several suggestions have been made in relation to this problem. Pareschi and Steedman (1987) describe what they call a 'lazy chart parser' intended to yield only one of each set of equivalent analyses by adopting a reduce-first parsing strategy, and invoking a special recovery procedure to avoid the backtracking that this strategy would otherwise necessitate. But Hepple (1987) shows that their algorithm is incomplete. Wittenburg (1987) presents an approach in which a combinatory grammar is compiled into one not exhibiting derivational equivalence. Such compilation seeks to avoid the problem of parsing with a grammar exhibiting derivational equivalence by arranging that the grammar used on-line does not have this property. The concern here however is management of parsing when the grammar used on-line does have the problematic property. Karttunen (1986) suggests a strategy in which every potential new edge is tested against the chart to see whether an existing analysis spanning the same region is equivalent. If one is found, the new analysis is discarded. However, because this check requires comparison with every edge spanning the relevant region, checking time increases with the number of such edges.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 64,
"end": 92,
"text": "Pareschi and Steedman (1987)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF9"
},
{
"start": 366,
"end": 379,
"text": "Hepple (1987)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF5"
},
{
"start": 422,
"end": 439,
"text": "Wittenburg (1987)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF12"
},
{
"start": 848,
"end": 864,
"text": "Karttunen (1986)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "(8)",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The solution we offer is one in which there is a notion of normal form derivation, and a set of contraction rules which reduce derivations to their normal forms, normal form derivations being those to which no contraction rule can apply. The contraction rules might be used in a number of ways (e.g. to transform one derivation into another, rather than recompute from the start, cf. Pareschi and Steedman) . The possibility emphasised here is one in which we ensure that a processing step does not create a non-normal form derivation. Any such derivation is dispensable, assuming exhaustive search: the normal form derivation to which it is equivalent, and which won't be excluded, will yield the same result. Thus the equivalence check can be to make sure that each derivation computed is a normal form, e.g. by checking that no step creates a form to which a contraction rule can apply. Unlike Karttunen's subsumption check this test does not become slower with the size of a chart. The test to see whether a derivation is normal form involves nothing but the derivation itself and the invarlant definition of normal form.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 384,
"end": 406,
"text": "Pareschi and Steedman)",
"ref_id": null
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "(8)",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The next section gives a general outline of reduction and normal forms. This is followed by an illustration in relation to typed combinatory logic, where we emphasise that the reduction constitutes a proof-reduction. We then describe how the notions can be applied to combinatory grammar to handle the problem of parsing and derivational equivalence, and we again note that if derivations are regarded as proofs, the method is an instantiation of proof-reduction.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "(8)",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "It is a common state of affairs for some terms of a language to be equivalent in that for the intended semantics, their interpretations are the same in all models. In such a circumstance it can be useful to elect normal forms which act as unique representatives of their equivalence class. For example, if terms can be transformed into normal forms, equivalence between terms can be equated with identity of normal forms. 1",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The usual way of defining normal forms is by 1For our purposes 'identity I can mean exact syntactic identity, and this simplifies discussion somewhat; in a system with bound variables such as the lambda-calculus, identity would mean identity up to renaming of bound variables. defining a relation l> ('contracts-to') of CONTRAC-TION between equivalent terms; a term X is said to be in NORMAL FORM if and only if there is no term Y such that X 1> Y. The contraction relation generates a reduction relation ~ ('reduces-to') and an equality relation --('equals') between terms as follows:",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(13) a. IfX I> YthenX_> Y b. X>X c. If X_> YandY_> Z thenX >_ Z (14) a. IfX I> YthenX=Y b. X=X c. If X= YandY= Z thenX= Z d. IfX= YthenY= X",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The equality relation is sound with respect to a semantic equivalence relation --if X = Y implies X = Y, and complete if X ---Y implies X --Y. It is a sufficient condition for soundness that the contraction relation is valid. Y is a normal form of X if and only if Y is a normal form and X _> Y. A sequence X0 I> X1 1> ..-I> Xn is called a REDUCTION (of X0 to X.).",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "We see from (14) that if there is a T such that P >_ T and Q >_ T, then P --Q (--T). In particular, if X and Y have the same normal form, then X --Y.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Suppose the relations of reduction and equality generated by the contraction relation have the following property:",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(15) Church-Rosser (C-R): If P ---Q then there is a T such that P >_ T and Q _> T.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "There follow as corollaries that if P and Q are distinct normal forms then P ~ Q, and that any normal form of a term is uniquefl If two terms X and Y have distinct normal forms P and Q, then X --PandY--Q, butP~Q, soX~ Y.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "2Suppose P and Q are distinct normal forms and that P ----Q. Because normal forms only reduce to themselves and P and Q are distinct, there is no term to which P and Q can both reduce. But C-R tells us that if P = Q, then there/a a term to which they can both reduce. And suppose that a term X has distinct normal forms P and Q; then X = P, X = Q, and P --Q. But by the first corollary, for distinct normal forms P and Q, P ~ Q.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "We have established that if two terms have the same normal form then they are equal and (given C-R) that if they have different normal forms then they are not equal, and that normal forms are unique. Suppose we also have the following property:",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(16) Strong Normalisation (SN): Every reduction is finite.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "This has the corollary (normalisation) that every term has a normal form. A sufficient condition to demonstrate SN would be to find a metric which assigns to each term a finite non-negative integer score, and to show that each application of a contraction decrements the score by a non-zero integral amount. It follows that any reduction of a term must be finite. Given both C-R and SN, equality is decidable: we can reduce any terms to their normal forms in a finite number of steps, and compare for identity.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Reduction and Normal Form",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "In the CL case, note for example the following equivalence (omitting types for the moment): These state that any term containing an occurrence of the form on the left can be transformed to one in which the occurrence is replaced by the form on the right. A form on the left is called a REDEX, the form on the right, its CONTRACTUM. To see the validity of the contraction relation defined (and the soundness of the consequent equality), note that the functional interpretations of a redex and a contractum are the same, and that by compositional ity, the interpretation of a term is unchanged by substitution of a subterm for an occurrence of a subterm with the same interpretation. An example of reduction of a term to its normal form is as follows:",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Norxizal Form and Proof-Reduction in Combinatory Logic",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(19) C I John' (B probably' walks n) I> I (B probably I walkd) Johnll> B probably ~ walk~ John' I> probably I (walks' John')",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Norxizal Form and Proof-Reduction in Combinatory Logic",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Returning to emphasise types, observe that they can be regarded as formulae of implicational logic. In fact the type schemes of the basic combinators in (2), together with a modus ponens rule corresponding to the application in (3b), provide an axiomatisation of relevant implication (see Morrill and Carpenter, 1987 , for discussion in relation to grammar): Consider the typed CL-terms in (4). For each of these, the tree of type formulae is a proof in implicational relevance logic. Corresponding to the term-reduction and normal form in (19), there is proof-reduction and a normal form for a proof over the language of types (see e.g. Hindley and Seldin, 1986) . There can be proof-contraction rules such as the following: Proof-reduction originated with Prawitz (1965) and is now a standard technique in logic. The suggestion of this paper is that if parse trees labelled with categories can be regarded as proofs over the language of categories, then the problem of parsing and derivational equivalence can be treated on the pattern of proof-reductlon. Strong equivalence and reduction is far more complex than weak equivalence and reduction, but unfortunately it is the former which is appropriate for the grammars. Later examples will thus differ in this respect from the one above. A second difference is that in the example above, combinators are axioms, and there is a single rule of application. In the grammar cases combinators are rules. Finally, grammar derivations have both a phonological interpretation (dependent on the order of the words), and a semantic interpretation. Since no derivations are equivalent if they produce a different sequence of words, derivation reduction must always preserve word order.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 289,
"end": 316,
"text": "Morrill and Carpenter, 1987",
"ref_id": "BIBREF8"
},
{
"start": 638,
"end": 663,
"text": "Hindley and Seldin, 1986)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF4"
},
{
"start": 758,
"end": 772,
"text": "Prawitz (1965)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF10"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Norxizal Form and Proof-Reduction in Combinatory Logic",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Consider a combinatory grammar containing the application rules, Forward Composition, and also Subject Type-Raising (24); the latter two enable association of a subject with an incomplete verb phrase; this is required in (25), as shown in (26). .>B",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Normal Form and Proof-Reduction in Combinatory Grammar",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "This grammar will allow many equivalent derivations, but consider the following contraction rules: Each contraction rule states that a derivation containing an occurrence of the redex can be transformed into an equivalent one in which the occurrence is replaced by the contractum. To see that the rules are valid, note that in each contraction rule constituent order is preserved, and that the determination of the root meaning in terms of the daughter meanings is (extensionally) equivalent under the functional interpretation of the combinators.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "x/v Y/Z z ,>B x/z x x/Y v/z z l>~ Y X (f(B ~y) ,) = (fx (ry,)) b. X/Y Y/Z Z/W X/Y Y/Z Z/W \u2022 >B >B X/Z 1>2 Y/W >B ,>B x/w x/",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Observe by analogy with combinatory logic that a derivation can be regarded as a proof over the language of categories, and that the derivationreduction defined above is a proof-reduction. So far as we are aware, the relations of reduction and equality generated observe the C-R corollaries that distinct normal forms are non-equal, and that normal forms are unique. We provid e the following reasoning to the effect that SN holds.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Assign to each derivation a score, depending on its binary and unary branching tree structure as follows:",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(28) a. An elementary tree has score 1 b. If a left subtree has score z and a right subtree has score y, the binary-branching tree formed from them has score 2z -t-y",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "c. If a subtree has score z then a unary-branching tree formed from it has score 2z",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "All derivations will have a finite score of at least 1. Consider the scores for the redex and contractum in each of the above. Let z, y, and z be the scores for the subtrees dominated by the leaves in left-to-right order. For I>1, the score of the redex is 2(2z\u00f7y)\u00f7z and that of its contractum is 2z-t-(2y + z): a decrement of 2z, and this is always non-zero because all scores are at least 1. The case of 1>2 is the same.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "In I>s the score of the redex is 2(2z) -t-y, that of the contractum 2~-t-y: also a proper decrement. So all reductions are finite, and there is the corollary that all derivations have normal forms.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Since all derivations have normal forms, we can safely limit attention in parsing to normal form derivations: for all the derivations excluded, there is an equivalent normal form which is not excluded. If not all derivations had normal forms, limitation to normal forms might lose those derivations in the grammar which do not have normal forms. The strategy to avoid unnecessary work can be to discontinue any derivation that contains a redex. The test is neutral as to whether the parsing algorithm is, e.g. top-down or bottom-up.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The seven derivations of John will see Mary in the grammar are shown below. Each occurrence of a redex is marked with a correspondingly labelled asterisk. It will be seen that of the seven logical possibilities, only one is now licensed: It will be seen that (33a) has (27b) as the special case n = 1, m = 1. Furthermore, if we admit a combinator B \u00b0 which is equivalent to the combinator f, and use this as the semantics for Forward Application, we can extend the generalised contraction rule (33) to have (27a) as a special case also (by allowing the values for m and n to be such that , ~_ 0; m > 1). It will be seen that again, every contraction results in a proper decrement of the score assigned, so that SN holds.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "In Morrill (1988) it is argued at length that even rules like generalised forward composition are not adequate to characterise the full range of extraction and coordination phenomena, and that deeper generalisations need to be expressed. In particular, a system is advocated in which more complex rules are derived from the basic rules of application by the use of metarules, like that in (34); these are similar to those of G azdar (1981), but with slash interpreted as the categorial operator (see also Geach, 1972, p485; Moo/tgat, 1987, plS) . Note for instance that applying Right Abstraction to Forward Application yields Steedman's Forward Composition primitive, and that successive application yields higher order compositions: Suppose we now assign scores as follows:",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 3,
"end": 17,
"text": "Morrill (1988)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF7"
},
{
"start": 505,
"end": 523,
"text": "Geach, 1972, p485;",
"ref_id": null
},
{
"start": 524,
"end": 544,
"text": "Moo/tgat, 1987, plS)",
"ref_id": null
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(38) a. An elementary tree has score I b. If a left subtree has score z and a right subtree has score y, the binary-branching tree formed from them has score z + 21/",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The score ofa redex will be x+2(y-i-2z) and that of its contractum (x + 2y) + 2z: a proper decrement, so SN holds and all derivations have normal forms as before. For the sentence John will see Mary, the grammar allows the set of derivations shown in (39). ",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "S/NP",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "We have offered a solution to the problem of parsing and derivational equivalence by introducing a notion of normal-form derivation. A definition of redex can be used to avoid computing nonnormal form derivations. Computing only normal form derivations is safe provided every non-normal form derivation has a normal form equivalent. By demonstrating strong normalisation for the examples given, we have shown that every derivation does have a normal form, and that consequently parsing with this method is complete in the sense that at least one member of each equivalence class is computed. In addition, it would be desirable to show that the Church-Rosser property holds, to guarantee that each equivalence class has a unique normal form. This would ensure that parsing with this method is optimal in the sense that for each equivalence class, only one derivation is computed.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Conclusion",
"sec_num": null
}
],
"back_matter": [],
"bib_entries": {
"BIBREF0": {
"ref_id": "b0",
"title": "On the Order of Words",
"authors": [
{
"first": "A",
"middle": [],
"last": "Ades",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "M",
"middle": [
"J"
],
"last": "Steedman",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1982,
"venue": "Linguistics and Philosophy",
"volume": "4",
"issue": "",
"pages": "517--558",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Ades, A. and Steedman, M. J. 1982. On the Or- der of Words. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4: 517- 558.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF1": {
"ref_id": "b1",
"title": "Combinatory logic, Volume I. North Holland",
"authors": [
{
"first": "H",
"middle": [
"B"
],
"last": "Curry",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "R",
"middle": [],
"last": "Feys",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "",
"middle": [],
"last": "Amsterdam",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "H",
"middle": [
"B"
],
"last": "Curry",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "J",
"middle": [
"R"
],
"last": "Hindley",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "J",
"middle": [
"P"
],
"last": "Seldin",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1958,
"venue": "Combinatory logic",
"volume": "II",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Curry, H. B. and Feys, R. 1958. Combinatory logic, Volume I. North Holland, Amsterdam. Curry, H. B., Hindley, J. R. and Seldin, J. P. 1972. Combinatory logic, Volume II. North Hol- land, Amsterdam.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF2": {
"ref_id": "b2",
"title": "Unbounded dependencies and coordinate structure",
"authors": [
{
"first": "G",
"middle": [],
"last": "Gazdar",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1981,
"venue": "Linguistic Inquiry",
"volume": "12",
"issue": "",
"pages": "155--184",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Gazdar, G. 1981. Unbounded dependencies and coordinate structure. Linguistic Inquiry, 12: 155- 184.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF3": {
"ref_id": "b3",
"title": "A program for syntax",
"authors": [
{
"first": "P",
"middle": [
"T"
],
"last": "Geach",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1972,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Geach, P. T. 1972. A program for syntax. In",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF4": {
"ref_id": "b4",
"title": "Introduction to combinators and h-calculus",
"authors": [
{
"first": "D",
"middle": [],
"last": "Davidson",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "G",
"middle": [],
"last": "Haman",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "",
"middle": [],
"last": "; D. Reidel",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "J",
"middle": [
"R"
],
"last": "Hindley",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "J",
"middle": [
"P"
],
"last": "Seldin",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1986,
"venue": "Semantics of Natural Language",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Davidson, D. and Haman, G. (eds.) Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: D. ReideL Hindley, J. R. and Seldin, J. P. 1986. Intro- duction to combinators and h-calculus. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF5": {
"ref_id": "b5",
"title": "Methods for Parsing Combinatory Grammars and the Spurious AmbiguiW Problem",
"authors": [
{
"first": "M",
"middle": [],
"last": "Hepple",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1987,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Hepple, M. 1987. Methods for Parsing Com- binatory Grammars and the Spurious AmbiguiW Problem. Masters Thesis, Centre for Cognitive Sci- ence, University of Edinburgh.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF6": {
"ref_id": "b6",
"title": "Paper presented at the Conference on Alternative Conceptions of Phrase Structure",
"authors": [
{
"first": "L",
"middle": [],
"last": "Karttunen",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1986,
"venue": "Moortgat, M. 1987. Lambek Categoria] Grammar and the Autonomy Thesis. INL Working Papers No. 87-03",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Karttunen, L. 1986. Radical Lexicallsm. Re- port No. CSLI-86-68, Center for the Study of Lan- guage and Information, December, 1986. Paper presented at the Conference on Alternative Con- ceptions of Phrase Structure, July 1986, New York. Moortgat, M. 1987. Lambek Categoria] Gram- mar and the Autonomy Thesis. INL Working Pa- pers No. 87-03, Instituut voor Nederlandse Lexi- cologie, Leiden, April, 1987.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF7": {
"ref_id": "b7",
"title": "Extraction and Coordination in Phrase Structure Grammar and Categorial Grammar",
"authors": [
{
"first": "G",
"middle": [],
"last": "Morrill",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1988,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Morrill, G. 1988. Extraction and Coordina- tion in Phrase Structure Grammar and Categorial Grammar. PhD Thesis, Centre for Cognitive Sci- ence, University of Edinburgh.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF8": {
"ref_id": "b8",
"title": "Compositionality, Implicational Logics, and Theories of Grammar",
"authors": [
{
"first": "G",
"middle": [],
"last": "Morrill",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "B",
"middle": [],
"last": "Carpenter",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1987,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Morrill, G. and Carpenter, B. 1987. Compo- sitionality, Implicational Logics, and Theories of Grammar. Research Paper No. EUCCS/RP-11, Centre for Cognitive Science, University of Edin- burgh, Edinburgh, June, 1987. To appear in Lin- guistics and Philosophy.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF9": {
"ref_id": "b9",
"title": "A Lazy Way to Chart-Parse with Extended Categorial Grammars",
"authors": [
{
"first": "R",
"middle": [],
"last": "Pareschi",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "M",
"middle": [
"J"
],
"last": "Steedman",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1987,
"venue": "Proceedinge of the \u00a3Sth Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "6--9",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Pareschi, R. and Steedman, M. J. 1987. A Lazy Way to Chart-Parse with Extended Catego- rial Grammars. In Proceedinge of the \u00a3Sth An- nual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics, Stanford University, Stanford, Ca., 6-9",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF10": {
"ref_id": "b10",
"title": "Dependency and Coordination in the Grammar of Dutch and English",
"authors": [
{
"first": "D",
"middle": [],
"last": "Prawitz",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "",
"middle": [],
"last": "Ahnqvist",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "Uppsala",
"middle": [],
"last": "Wiksell",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "M",
"middle": [],
"last": "Steedman",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1965,
"venue": "",
"volume": "61",
"issue": "",
"pages": "523--568",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Prawitz, D. 1965. Natural Deduction: A Proof Theoretical Study. Ahnqvist and Wiksell, Uppsala. Steedman, M. 1985. Dependency and Coordi- nation in the Grammar of Dutch and English. Lan- guage, 61: 523-568.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF11": {
"ref_id": "b11",
"title": "Combinatory Grammars and Parasitic Gaps. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory",
"authors": [
{
"first": "M",
"middle": [],
"last": "Steedman",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1987,
"venue": "",
"volume": "5",
"issue": "",
"pages": "403--439",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Steedman, M. 1987. Combinatory Grammars and Parasitic Gaps. Natural Language and Lin- guistic Theory, 5: 403-439.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF12": {
"ref_id": "b12",
"title": "Predictive Combinators: a Method for Efficient Processing of Combinatory Categorial Grammar",
"authors": [
{
"first": "K",
"middle": [],
"last": "Wittenburg",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1987,
"venue": "Proceedings of the ~5th",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Wittenburg, K. 1987. Predictive Combinators: a Method for Efficient Processing of Combinatory Categorial Grammar. In Proceedings of the ~5th",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF13": {
"ref_id": "b13",
"title": "Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics",
"authors": [],
"year": 1987,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Annual Meeting of the Association for Computa- tional Linguistics, Stanford University, Stanford, Ca., 6-9 July, 1987.",
"links": null
}
},
"ref_entries": {
"FIGREF2": {
"text": "17) B probably ~ walks ~ John ~ --probably ~ (walks' John #)We may have the following contraction rules:",
"num": null,
"type_str": "figure",
"uris": null
},
"FIGREF5": {
"text": "Before proceeding to the grammar cases, a couple of remarks are in order. The equivalence addressed by the reductions above is not strong (extensional), but what is called weak equivalence. For example the following pairs (whose types have been omitted) are distinct weak normal forms, but are extensionally equivalent:(22) a. B (B probablyanecessarily l) walks l b. B probablyW(B necessarilylwalks s) (23) a. B I walks I b. walks'",
"num": null,
"type_str": "figure",
"uris": null
},
"FIGREF7": {
"text": "Tx) y) ----(b x y)",
"num": null,
"type_str": "figure",
"uris": null
},
"FIGREF8": {
"text": "Consider now the combinatory grammar obtained by replacing Forward Composition by the Generallsed Forward Composition rule (31a}, whose semantics B\" is recursively defined in terms of B as shown in (31b). the adoption of this rule with replacement of the contraction rule (27b) by the following generalised version:(ss) a. X/Y WZz\"'/Zm Zm/Wz\"'/W. ,)B m Y/Zz.. -/Zm -~B n x/zz--./z~.z/wz-../Wn X/Y Y/Zz---/Z~ Zm/Wz.../Wn ,~B n l>g Y/ZI.../Zm.1/Wl.../Wn .)Bin+n-1 X/Zr--/Zm.1/Wr--/Wn b. (B n (Bm x y) ,) = (B ('r'+\"-*) x (B\" y ~-)) for, > I; m>_l",
"num": null,
"type_str": "figure",
"uris": null
},
"FIGREF9": {
"text": "==~ R~b: X+Y/Z=>V/Z (where (R g x y) --= gx(yz) )",
"num": null,
"type_str": "figure",
"uris": null
},
"FIGREF10": {
"text": "35) a. Rf: X/Y + Y/Z ::~ X/Z b. R(Rf): X/Y + Y/Z/W ::~ X/Z/W Applying Right Abstraction to Backward Application yields a combinator capable of assembling a subject and incomplete verb phrase, without first type-raising the subject: Note that for this approach, the labelling for a rule used in a derivation is precisely the combinator that forms the semantics for that rule.) Consider a grammar with just the application rules and Right Abstraction. Let R'~ be R(... 1%(~6)...) with n _> 0 occurrences of R. Instead of the contraction rules earlier we may have: .../w.b. (R\"~b x (Rnf y z)) --(R\"r (Re x y) z)",
"num": null,
"type_str": "figure",
"uris": null
},
"FIGREF11": {
"text": "we can see that only one derivation, (39b), contains no redexes, and it is thus the only admissible normal form derivation. The derivations are related by the contraction relation as follows:",
"num": null,
"type_str": "figure",
"uris": null
}
}
}
}