Benjamin Aw
Add updated pkl file v3
6fa4bc9
{
"paper_id": "E95-1001",
"header": {
"generated_with": "S2ORC 1.0.0",
"date_generated": "2023-01-19T10:31:31.491340Z"
},
"title": "On Reasoning with Ambiguities",
"authors": [
{
"first": "Uwe",
"middle": [],
"last": "Reyle",
"suffix": "",
"affiliation": {
"laboratory": "",
"institution": "University of Stuttgart",
"location": {
"addrLine": "Azenbergstr.12",
"postCode": "D-70174",
"settlement": "Stuttgart",
"country": "Germany"
}
},
"email": "[email protected]"
}
],
"year": "",
"venue": null,
"identifiers": {},
"abstract": "The paper adresses the problem of reasoning with ambiguities. Semantic representations are presented that leave scope relations between quantifiers and/or other operators unspecified. Truth conditions are provided for these representations and different consequence relations are judged on the basis of intuitive correctness. Finally inference patterns are presented that operate directly on these underspecified structures, i.e. do not rely on any translation into the set of their disambiguations.",
"pdf_parse": {
"paper_id": "E95-1001",
"_pdf_hash": "",
"abstract": [
{
"text": "The paper adresses the problem of reasoning with ambiguities. Semantic representations are presented that leave scope relations between quantifiers and/or other operators unspecified. Truth conditions are provided for these representations and different consequence relations are judged on the basis of intuitive correctness. Finally inference patterns are presented that operate directly on these underspecified structures, i.e. do not rely on any translation into the set of their disambiguations.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Abstract",
"sec_num": null
}
],
"body_text": [
{
"text": "Whenever we hear a sentence or read a text we build up mental representations in which some aspects of the meaning of the sentence or text are left underspecified. And if we accept what we have heard or read as true, then we will use these underspecified representations as premisses for arguments. The challenge is, therefore, to equip underspecified semantic representations with well-defined truth conditions and to formulate inference patterns for these representations that follow the arguments that we judge as intuitively correct. Several proposals exist for the definition of the language, but only very few authors have addressed the problem of defining a logic of ambiguous reasoning. [8] considers lexical ambiguities and investigates structural properties of a number of consequence relations based on an abstract notion of coherency. It is not clear, however, how this approach could be extended to other kinds of ambiguities, especially quantifier scope ambiguities and ambiguities triggered by plural NPs. [1] , [7] and [6] deal with ambiguities of the latter kind. They give construction rules and define truth conditions according to which an underspecified representation of an ambiguous sentence is true if one of its disambiguations is. The problem of reasoning is adressed only in [5] and [7] . [5] 's inference schemata yield a very weak logic only; and [7] 's deductive component is too strong. Being weak and strong depends of course on the underlying consequence relation. Neither [5] nor [7] make any att-empt to systematically derive the consequence relation that holds for reasoning with ambiguities on the basis of an empirical discussion of intuitively valid arguments. The present paper starts out with such a discussion in Section 2. Section 3 gives a brief introduction to the theory of UDRSs. It gives a sketch of the principles to construct UDRSs and shows how scope ambiguities of quantifiers and negation are represented in an underspecified way. As the rules of inference presented in [7] turn out to be sound also with respect to the consequence relation defined in Section 2 these rules (for the fragment without disjunction) will be discussed only briefly in Section 4. The change in the deduction system that is imposed by the new consequence relation comes with the rules of proof. Section 5 shows that it is no longer possible to use rules like Conditionalisation or Reductio ad Absurdum when we deal with real ambiguities in the goal. An alternative set of rules is presented in Section 6.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 695,
"end": 698,
"text": "[8]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF7"
},
{
"start": 1021,
"end": 1024,
"text": "[1]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF0"
},
{
"start": 1027,
"end": 1030,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
},
{
"start": 1035,
"end": 1038,
"text": "[6]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF5"
},
{
"start": 1302,
"end": 1305,
"text": "[5]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF4"
},
{
"start": 1310,
"end": 1313,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
},
{
"start": 1316,
"end": 1319,
"text": "[5]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF4"
},
{
"start": 1376,
"end": 1379,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
},
{
"start": 1506,
"end": 1509,
"text": "[5]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF4"
},
{
"start": 1514,
"end": 1517,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
},
{
"start": 2023,
"end": 2026,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Introduction",
"sec_num": "1"
},
{
"text": "In this section we will discuss some sample arguments containing ambiguous expressions in the data as well as in the goal. We consider three kinds of ambiguities: lexical ambiguities, quantifier scope ambiguities, and ambiguities with respect to distributive/collective readings of plural noun phrases. The discussion of the arguments will show that the meaning of ambiguous sentences not only depends on the set of its disambiguations. Their meanings also depend on the context, especially on other occurrences of ambiguities. Each disambiguation of an ambiguous sentence may be correlated to disambiguations of other ambiguous sentences such that the choice of the first disambiguation also determines the choice of the latter ones, and vice versa. Thus the representation of ambiguities requires some means to implement these correlations. To see that this is indeed the case let us start discussing some consequence relations that come to mind when dealing with ambiguous reasoning. The first one we will consider is the one that allows to derive a(n ambiguous) conclusion 7 from a set of (ambiguous) premisses F if some disambiguation of 7 follows from all readings of F. Assuming that 5 and 5~ are operators mapping a set of ambiguous representations a onto one of its disambiguations a ~ or a ~' we may represent this by. (1) v~3~'(r ~ p \u00a2'). Obviously (1) is the relation we get if we interpret ambiguities as being equivalent to the disjunctions of their readings. To interpret ambiguities in this way is, however, not correct. For ambiguities in the goal this is witnessed by (2).",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 1329,
"end": 1332,
"text": "(1)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF0"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Consequence Relations",
"sec_num": "2"
},
{
"text": "(2) ~ Everybody slept or everybody didnlt sleep. Intuitively (2) is contingent, but would -according to the relation in (1) -be classified as a tautology. In this case the consequence relation in (3) gives the correct result and therefore seems to be preferable.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 196,
"end": 199,
"text": "(3)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF2"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Consequence Relations",
"sec_num": "2"
},
{
"text": "(3) v v l(r p \u00a2')",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Consequence Relations",
"sec_num": "2"
},
{
"text": "But there is another problem with (3). It does not fulfill Reflexivity, which (1) does. Reflexivity F ~ \u00a2, if \u00a2 e F To do justice to both, the examples in (2) and Reflexivity, we would have to interpret ambiguous sentences in the data also as conjunctions of their readings, i.e. accept (4) as consequence relation. (4) 35'3~(r ~ ~ 7 ~') But this again contradicts intuitions. (4) would support the inferences in (5) , which are intuitively not correct.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 155,
"end": 158,
"text": "(2)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF1"
},
{
"start": 316,
"end": 319,
"text": "(4)",
"ref_id": null
},
{
"start": 413,
"end": 416,
"text": "(5)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF4"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Consequence Relations",
"sec_num": "2"
},
{
"text": "a. There is a big plant in front of my house. (5) ~ There is a big building in front of my house.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Consequence Relations",
"sec_num": "2"
},
{
"text": "b. Everybody didn't sleep. ~ Everybody was awake. c. Three boys got \u00a310. ~ Three boys got \u00a310 each. Given the examples in (5) we are back to (1) and may think that ambiguities in the data are interpreted as disjunctions of their readings. But irrespective of the incompatibility with Reflexivity this picture cannot be correct either, because it distroys the intuitively valid inference in (6) . (6) If the students get \u00a310 then they buy books.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 390,
"end": 393,
"text": "(6)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF5"
},
{
"start": 396,
"end": 399,
"text": "(6)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF5"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Consequence Relations",
"sec_num": "2"
},
{
"text": "The students get \u00a310. ~ They buy books. This example shows that disambiguation is not an operation 5 that takes (a set of) isolated sentences. Ambiguous sentences of the same type have to be disambiguated simultaneously. 1 Thus the meaning of 1We will not give a classification or definition of ambiguities of the same type here. Three major classes will consist of lexical ambiguities, ambiguities with respect to distributive/collective readings of plural noun phrases, and quantifier scope ambiguities. As regards the last type we assume on the one hand that only sentences with the same argument structure and the same set of readings can be of the same type. More precisely, if two sentences are of the same type with respect to quantifier scope ambiguities, then the labels of their UDRS's the premise of (6) is given by (7b) not by (7a), where al represents the first and a2 the second reading of the second sentence of (6). It was completely delapidated. John and Mary bought a house. If the inference is now seen as the result of R's task to make the first sentence explicit (which of course is trivial here), then the goal will not be ambiguous, because it simply is another occurrence of the representation in the data, and, therefore, will carry the same correlation index. In the second case, i.e. the case where the goal results from R's processing some external input, there is no guarantee for such a correlation. R might consider the goal as ambiguous, and hence will not accept it as a consequence. (B might after all have had in mind just that reading of the sentence that is not part of R's knowledge.) must be ordered isomorphically. On the other hand two sentences may carry an ambiguity of the same type if one results from the other by applying Detachment to a universally quantified NP (see Section 4).",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Consequence Relations",
"sec_num": "2"
},
{
"text": "EQUATION",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [
{
"start": 0,
"end": 8,
"text": "EQUATION",
"ref_id": "EQREF",
"raw_str": "V (a2 b)) ^ V",
"eq_num": "("
}
],
"section": "a. ((al b)",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "We will distinguish between these two situations by requiring the provability relation to respect indices. The rule of direct proof will then be an instance of Reflexivity: F t-7i if ~'i E F.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "a. ((al b)",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The base for unscoped representations proposed in [7] is the separation of information about the structure of a particular semantic form and of the content of the information bits the semantic form combines. In case the semantic form is given by a DRS its structure is given by the hierarchy of subDRSs, that is determined by ==v, -% V and (>. We will represent this hierarchy explicitly by the subordination relation <. The semantic content of a DRS consists of the set of its discourse referents and its conditions. To be more precise, we express the structural information by a language with one predicate _< that relates individual constants l, called labels. The constants are names for DRS's. < corresponds to the subordination relation between them, i.e. the set of labels with < is a upper semilattice with one-element (denoted by/7-). Let us consider the DRSs (11) and (12) representing the two readings of (10). The following representations make the distinction between structure and content more explicit. The subordination relation <_ is read from bottom to top. 14, because it only contains the information common to both, (11) and (12). In any case ORD lists only the subordination relations that are neither implicitly contained in the partial order nor determined by complex UDRSconditions. This means that (15) implicitly contains the information that, e.g., res(/2) < lT, and also that res(/2) ~ 12, res(ll) ~_ lT and scope(ll) ~ lT.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 50,
"end": 53,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "A short introduction to UDRSs",
"sec_num": "3"
},
{
"text": "In this paper we consider the fragment of UDRSs without disjunction. For reason of space we cannot consider problems that arise when indefinites occurring in subordinate clauses are interpreted specifically. 2 We will, therefore assume that indefinites behave like generalized quantifers in that their scope is clause bounded too, i.e. require l<_l' for all i in clause (ii.c) of the following definition. ~These problems axe discussed extensively in [7] and the solution given there can be taken over to the rules presented here.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 208,
"end": 209,
"text": "2",
"ref_id": "BIBREF1"
},
{
"start": 451,
"end": 454,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "A short introduction to UDRSs",
"sec_num": "3"
},
{
"text": "(i) (I:<UK,C K U C~>,res(1), scope(l),ORDt) is a UDRS-component, if (UK, CSK)",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Definition 1:",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "3Whenever convenient we will simply use implicative conditions of the form ll =:~ /2, to represent universally quantified NPs (instead of their generalized quantifier representation (every, 11, /2) ). ",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Definition 1:",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The four inference rules needed for the fragment without generalized quantifiers 6 and disjunction are non-empty universe (NeU), detachment (DET), ambiguity introduction (AI), and ambiguity elimination (DIFF). NeU allows to add any finite collection of discourse referents to a DRS universe. It reflects the assumption that there is of necessity one thing, i.e. that we consider only models with non-empty universes. DET is a generalization of modus ponens. It allows to add (a variant of) the consequent of an implication (or the scope of a universally quantified condition) to the DRS in which the condition occurs if the antecedent (restrictor) can be mapped to this DRS. AI allows one to add an ambiguous representation to the data, if the data already contains all of its disambiguations. And an application of DIFF reduces the set of readings of an underspecified representation in the presence of negations of some of its readings. The formulations of NeU, DET and DIFF needed for the consequence relation (8) defined in Section 2 of this paper are just refinements of the formulations needed for the consequence relation (1) . As the latter case isextensively discussed in [7] and a precise and complete formulation of the rules is also given there we will restrict ourselves to the refinements needed to adapt these rules to the new consequence relation. As there is nothing more to mention about NeU we start with DET. We first present a formulation of DET for DRSs. It is an extended formulation of standard DET as it allows for applications not only at the top level of a DRS but at levels of any depth. Correctness of this extension is shown in [4] . DET Suppose a DRS K contains a condition of the form K1 ::~ K2 such that K1 may be embedded into K by a function f, where K is the merge of all the DRSs to which K is subordinate. Then we may add K~ to K, where K~ results from K2 by replacing all occurrences of discourse referents of UK2 by new ones and the discourse referents x declared in UK1 by f(x). We will generalize DET to UDRSs such that the structure that results from an application of DET to a UDRS is again a UDRS, i.e. directly represents some natural language sentence. We, therefore, incorporate the task of what is usually done by a rule of thinning into the formulation of DET itself and also into the following definition of embedding. We define an embedding f of a UDRS into a UDRS to be a function that maps labels to labels and discourse referents to discourse referents while preserving all conditions in which they occur. We assume that f is one-to-one when f is restricted to the set of discour-6We will use implicative conditions of the form (=}, 11, 12), to represent universally quantified NPs (instead of their generalized quantifier representation (every, Zl, 12)).",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 1129,
"end": 1132,
"text": "(1)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF0"
},
{
"start": 1181,
"end": 1184,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
},
{
"start": 1658,
"end": 1661,
"text": "[4]",
"ref_id": null
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Inference",
"sec_num": "4"
},
{
"text": "se referents occurring in proper sub-universes. Only discourse referents occurring in the universe associated with 1T may be identified by f. We do not assume that the restriction of f to the set of labels is oneto-one also. But f must preserve -~, :=> and V, i.e. respect the following restrictions. }-At least one problem preoccupies John. (16) shows that DET may only be applied to a condition 7 occurring in l:K, if there is no component l':K I such that the distinguished condition l':7' of K' is either a monotone decreasing quantifier or a negation, and such that for some disambiguation of the clause in which 7 occurs we get l <_ scope(l').",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Inference",
"sec_num": "4"
},
{
"text": "As the negation of a monotone decreasing quantifier is monotone increasing and two negations neutralize each other the easiest way to implement the restriction is to assign polarities to UDRS components and restrict applications of DET to components with positive polarity as follows. The scheme for DET allows the arguments of the implicative condition to which it is applied still to be ambiguous. The discussion of example (6) in Section 2 focussed on the ambiguity of its antecedent only. (We ignored the ambiguity of the consequent there.) To discuss the case of ambiguous consequents we consider the the following argument.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 426,
"end": 429,
"text": "(6)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF5"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Inference",
"sec_num": "4"
},
{
"text": "(17)If the chairman talks, everybody doesn't sleep.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Inference",
"sec_num": "4"
},
{
"text": "The chairman talks. ~-Everybody doesn't sleep.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Inference",
"sec_num": "4"
},
{
"text": "There is a crucial difference between (17) and (6) :",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 47,
"end": 50,
"text": "(6)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF5"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Inference",
"sec_num": "4"
},
{
"text": "The truth of the conclusion in (17) depends on the fact that it is derived from the conditional. It, therefore, must be treated as correlated with the consequent of the conditional under any disambiguation. No non-correlated disambiguations are allowed. To ensure this we must have some means to represent 7A general treatment of n-ary quantification within the theory of UDRSs has still to be worked out. In [6] it is shown how cumulative quantification may be treated using identification of labels. the 'history' of the clauses that are added to a set of data. As (8) suggests this could be done by coindexing K:l,1 and/Cf(ln) in the representation of (17). In contrast to the obligatory coindexing in the case of (17) the consequence relation in (8) does allow for non-correlated interpretations in the case of (2). Such interpretations naturally occur if, e.g., the conditional and the minor premiss were introduced by very distinct parts of a text from which the database had been constructed. In such cases the interpreter may assume that the contexts in which the two sentences occurred are independent of each other. He, therefore, leaves leeway for the possibility that (later on) each context could be provided with more information in such a way that those interpretations trigger different disambiguations of the two occurrences. In such cases \"crossed interpretations\" must be allowed, and any application of DET must be refused by contraindexing -except the crossed interpretations can be shown to be equivalent. For the sake of readability we present the rule only for the propositional case.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 409,
"end": 412,
"text": "[6]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF5"
},
{
"start": 567,
"end": 570,
"text": "(8)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF7"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Inference",
"sec_num": "4"
},
{
"text": "But the interpreter could also adopt the strategy to accept the argument also in case of non-correlated interpretations without checking the validity of ai\u00a2* ak. In this case he will conclude that fit holds under the proviso that he might revise this inference if there will be additional information that forces him to disambiguate in a non-correlated way. If then ai 4:~ ak does not hold he must be able to give up the conclusion nit and every other argument that was based on it. To accomodate this strategy we need more than just coindexing. We need means to represent the structure of whole proofs. As we have labels available in our language we may do this by adopting the techniques of labelled deductive systems ( [3] ). For reasons of space we will not go into this in further detail. The next inference rule, AI, allows one to introduce ambiguities. It contrasts with the standard rule of disjunction introduction in that it allows for the introduction of a UDRS a that is underspecified with respect to the two readings al and a2 only if both, al and as, are contained in the data. This shows once more that ambiguities are not treated as disjunctions. Ambiguitiy Introduction Let or1 and a2 be two UDRSs of A that differ only w.r.t, their ORDs. Then we may add a UDRS a3 to A that is like al but has the intersection of ORD and ORD ~ as ordering of its labels. The index of aa is new to A. We give an example to show how AI and DET interact in the case of non-correlated readings: Suppose the data A consists of a~, 0\"2 and a3 ~ % We want to derive 3'. We apply AI to al and 62 and add au to A. As the index of a3 is new we must check whether al ~=> a2 can be derived from A. Because A contains both of them the proof succeeds. The last rule of inference, DIFF, eliminates ambiguities on the basis of structural differences in the ordering relations. Suppose ~1 and c~2 are a underspecified representations with three scope bearing components 11, 12, and 13. Assume further that al has readings that correspond to the following orders of these components: (h, /2, 11), (h, h, ll), and (h, ll, /3), whereas a2 is ambiguous between (/2, /3, /1) and (/2, ll, /3). Suppose now that the data contains al and the negation of a2. Then this set of data is equivalentto the reading given by (/3, /2, 11). To see that this holds the structural difference between the structures ORD,~ and ORD~ has to be calculated. The structural difference between two structures ORD~ and ORDa2 is the partial order that satisfies ORD~ but not ORD~2, if there is any; and it is falsity if there is no such order. Thus the notion of structural difference generalizes the traditional notion of inconsistency. Again a precise formulation of DIFF is given in [7] .",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 722,
"end": 725,
"text": "[3]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF2"
},
{
"start": 2741,
"end": 2744,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "A oq =~ fl.i o~k i = k V (i # k A A F-c~i 4:~ c~k) at",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Rules of proof are deduction rules that allow us to reduce the complexity of the goal by accomplishing /~ subproof. We will consider COND(itionalization) and R(eductio)A(d)A(bsurdum) and show that they may not be applied in the case of ambiguous goals (i.e. goals in which no operator has widest scope). Suppose we want to derive everybody didn't snore from everybody didn't sleep and the fact that snoring implies sleeping. I.e. we want to carry out the proof in (18), where ORD = {13 < scope(ll), 13 ~ scope(12), 15 <_ scope(14)} and ORIY = {Is < scope(17), Is < scope(16)}. ",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Proof",
"sec_num": "5"
},
{
"text": "Let us try to apply rules of proof to reduce the complexity of the goal. We use the extensions of COND and RAA given in [7] . There use is quite simple. If we tried to keep the reduction-of-the-goal strategy we would have to perform the disambiguation steps to formulas in the data that the order of application on COND and RAA triggers. And in addition we would have to check all possible orders, not only one. Hence we would perform exactly the same set of proofs that would be needed if we represented ambiguous sentences by sets of formulas. Nothing would have been gained with respect to any traditional approach.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 120,
"end": 123,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Proof",
"sec_num": "5"
},
{
"text": "We thus conclude that applications of COND and RAA are only possible if either =v or -, has wide scope in the goal. In this case standard formulations of COND and RAA may be applied even if the goal is ambiguous at some lower level of structure.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Proof",
"sec_num": "5"
},
{
"text": "In case the underspecification occurs with respect to the relative scope of immediate daughters of 1T, however, we must find some other means to relate non-identical UDRSs in goal and data. What we need are rules for UDRSs that generalize the success case for atoms within ordinary deduction systems.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Rules of Proof",
"sec_num": "5"
},
{
"text": "The inference in (18) can be realised very easily if we allow components of UDRSs that are marked negative to be replaced by components with a smaller denotation. Likewise components of UDRSs that are marked positive may be replaced by components with a larger denotation. If the component to be replaced is the restrictor of a generalized quantifier, then in addition to the polarity marking the soundness of such substitutions depends on the persistence property of the quantifier. In the framework of UDRSs persistence of quantifiers has to be defined relative to the context in which they occur. Let NPi be a persistent (anti-persistent) NP. Then NPi is called persistent (anti-persistent) in clause S, if sIf we would treat ambiguous clauses as the disjunctions of their meanings, i.e. take the consequence relation in (1) , then this disambiguation could be compensated for by applying RESTART (see [7] for details). But relative to the consequence relation under (8) RESTART is not sound! this property is preserved under each disambiguation of S. So everybody is anti-persistent in (19e), but not in (19a), because the wide scope reading for the negation blocks the inference in (19b). It is not persistent in (19c) nor in (19d).",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 824,
"end": 827,
"text": "(1)",
"ref_id": "BIBREF0"
},
{
"start": 905,
"end": 908,
"text": "[7]",
"ref_id": "BIBREF6"
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Deduction rules for top-level ambiguities",
"sec_num": "6"
},
{
"text": "(19)a. Everybody didn't come.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Deduction rules for top-level ambiguities",
"sec_num": "6"
},
{
"text": "b. Everybody didn't come. Every woman didn't come. c. More than half the problems were solved by everybody. d. It is not true that everybody didn't come. e. Some problem was solved by everybody. The main rule of inference for UDRSs is the following R(eplacement)R(ule). RR Whenever some UDRS K:~-occurs in a UDRSdatabase A and A I-K:~->>/C~ holds, then K:g may be added to A. RR is based on the following substitution rule. The >>-rules are given below. SUBST Let hK be a DRS component occurring in some UDRS )U, A a UDRS-database. Let K:' be the UDRS that results from K: by substituting K' for K. Then A KK: >>/C', if (i) or (ii) holds.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Deduction rules for top-level ambiguities",
"sec_num": "6"
},
{
"text": "(i) l has positive polarity and A K K >> K'. (ii) l has negative polarity and A K K' >> K.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Deduction rules for top-level ambiguities",
"sec_num": "6"
},
{
"text": "Schematically we represent the rule (for the case of positive polarity) as follows.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Deduction rules for top-level ambiguities",
"sec_num": "6"
},
{
"text": "For UDRS-components we have the following rule. >> DRS: A K K>>K' if there is a function f: UK--r UK, such that for all 7' E CK, there is a \"[ E CK with A ~-f(7)>>7'. 9 Complex conditions are dealt with by the following set of rules. Except for persistence properties they are still independent of the meaning of any particular generalized quantifier. The success of the rules can be achieved in two ways. Either by recursively applying the >>-rules. Or, by proving the implicative condition which will guarantee soundness of SUBST.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "3-+' l+:K if A K l+:K >> l+:K I A, IC~-+--, l+:K '",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "A F-(~,ll,12)>>(~,l~,l~) if A K Kl~ >> K:t~, or A K (--+,L:tl,/Ct,) .",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": ">>=\u00a2~:",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "(i) A K The following rules involve lexical meaning of words. We give some examples of determiner rules to indicate how we may deal with the logic of quantifiers in this rule set. Rules for nouns and verbs refer to a further inference relation, t -n. This relation takes the meaning postulates into account that a particular lexical theory associates with particular word meanings.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": ">>Q:",
"sec_num": "2."
},
{
"text": ">> Lex: The formulation of this rule is very general. In the simplest case it allows one to derive a sentence where an indefinite quantifier is interpreted non-specifically from an interpretation where it is assigned a specific meaning. If the specific/non-specific distinction is due to a universally quantified NP then the rule uses the fact that (a,l, s}~(every, l, s) holds. As other scope bearing elements may end up between the indefinite and the universal in some disambiguation the rule may only be applied, if these elements behave exactly the same way as the universal does, i.e. allow the indefinite to be read non-specifically. In case such an element is another universally quantified NP we thus may apply the rule, but we cannot apply it is a negation.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": ">>Q:",
"sec_num": "2."
},
{
"text": "(i) (",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": ">>Q:",
"sec_num": "2."
},
{
"text": "The paper has shown that it is possible to reason with ambiguities in a natural, direct and intuitively correct way.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Conclusion and Further Perspectives",
"sec_num": "7"
},
{
"text": "The fact that humans are able to reason with ambiguities led to a natural distinction between deduction systems that apply rules of proof to reduce the complexity of a goal and systems of logic that are tailored directly for natural language interpretation and reasoning. Human interpreters seem to use both systems when they perform reasoning tasks. We know that we cannot surmount undecidability (in a non-adhoc way) if we take quantifiers and/or connectives as logical devices in the traditional sense. But as the deduction rules for top-level ambiguities given here present an extension of Aristotelian syllogism metamathematical results about their complexity will be of great interest as well as the proof of a completeness theorem. Apart from this research the use of the rule system within the task of natural language understanding is under investigation. It seems that the Replacement Rules are particularly suited to do special reasoning tasks neccessary to disambiguate lexical ambiguities, because most of the deductive processes needed there are independent of any quantificational structure of the sentences containing the ambiguous item.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Conclusion and Further Perspectives",
"sec_num": "7"
}
],
"back_matter": [
{
"text": "The ideas of this paper where presented, first at an international workshop of the SFB 340 \"Sprachtheo-~etisehe Grundlagen der Computerlinguistik\" in October 1993, and second, at a workshop on 'Deduction and Language' that took place at SOAS, London, in spring 1994. I am particularly grateful for comments made by participants of these workshops.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Acknowledgements",
"sec_num": null
}
],
"bib_entries": {
"BIBREF0": {
"ref_id": "b0",
"title": "Monotonic semantic interpretation",
"authors": [
{
"first": "Hiyan",
"middle": [],
"last": "Alshawi",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "Richard",
"middle": [],
"last": "Crouch",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1992,
"venue": "Proceedings of ACL",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "32--39",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Hiyan Alshawi and Richard Crouch. Monotonic se- mantic interpretation. In Proceedings of ACL, pages 32-39, Newark, Delaware, 1992.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF1": {
"ref_id": "b1",
"title": "Principle based semantics for hpsg",
"authors": [
{
"first": "Anette",
"middle": [],
"last": "Frank",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "Uwe",
"middle": [],
"last": "Reyle",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1995,
"venue": "Proceedings of EACL 95",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Anette Frank and Uwe Reyle. Principle based seman- tics for hpsg. In Proceedings of EACL 95, Dublin, 1995.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF2": {
"ref_id": "b2",
"title": "Labelled deductive systems",
"authors": [
{
"first": "Dov",
"middle": [],
"last": "Gabbay",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1994,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Dov Gabbay. Labelled deductive systems. Technical report, Max Planck Institut fiir Informatik, 1994.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF4": {
"ref_id": "b4",
"title": "Scope ambiguity and inference",
"authors": [
{
"first": "Massimo",
"middle": [],
"last": "Poesio",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1991,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Massimo Poesio. Scope ambiguity and inference. Technical report, University of Rochester, N.Y., 1991.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF5": {
"ref_id": "b5",
"title": "Monotonic disambiguation and plural pronoun resolution",
"authors": [
{
"first": "Uwe",
"middle": [],
"last": "Reyle",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": null,
"venue": "CSLI Lecture Notes: Semantic Ambiguity and Underspecification",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Uwe Reyle. Monotonic disambiguation and plural pronoun resolution. In Kees van Deemter and Stan- ley Peters, editors, CSLI Lecture Notes: Semantic Ambiguity and Underspecification.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF6": {
"ref_id": "b6",
"title": "Dealing with ambiguities by underspecification: Construction, representation, and deduction",
"authors": [
{
"first": "Uwe",
"middle": [],
"last": "Reyle",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1993,
"venue": "Journal of Semantics",
"volume": "10",
"issue": "2",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Uwe Reyle. Dealing with ambiguities by underspecifi- cation: Construction, representation, and deduction. Journal of Semantics, 10(2), 1993.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF7": {
"ref_id": "b7",
"title": "On the Composisiton of Meaning",
"authors": [
{
"first": "",
"middle": [],
"last": "Kees Van Deemter",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1991,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Kees van Deemter. On the Composisiton of Meaning. PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam, 1991.",
"links": null
}
},
"ref_entries": {
"FIGREF0": {
"text": "(10) Everybody didn't pay attention. (11) I hum:n(x) ] =~ ] .~[x pay attention] I I (12) -, hum:n(x) I =*z I x pay attention ] ]",
"num": null,
"uris": null,
"type_str": "figure"
},
"FIGREF1": {
"text": "is a DRS containing standard DRS-conditions only, and C~: is one of the following sets of labelled DRS-conditions, where//1 and/(2 are standard DRSs, Qx is a generalized quantification over x, and l' is the upper bound of a (subordinate) UDRS-clause (l':(7o,...,Tn),ORD~) (defined below). (a) {}, or {sub(l')} (b) {l 1 ::~/2, ll :K1,/2:1(2}, or {ll ~ 12,11 :K1, /2 :K2,11 :sub(l') } (c) {(Off1,/2), l, :K1,/2:K2}, or{(Q, 11,12), ll.'Ki, 12K2, ll :sub(l') } } 3 (d) ,{\",l,, l, :K1}If C~ \u00a2 {} then 11 ~ /2, (Qzll,/2), or -~11 is called distinguished condition of K, referred to by l:7. res and scope are functions on the set of labels, and ORDt is a partial order of labels, res(l), scope(l), and ORDt are subject to the following restrictions:",
"num": null,
"uris": null,
"type_str": "figure"
},
"FIGREF2": {
"text": "(a) (a) If-~11E C~:, then res(l) = scope(1) = 11 and ll<l E ORDI. 4(f~) If (~, 11,12)E C~:, or Q~ll, 12E C~, then res(1) = 11, scope(1) = 12, and ll<l, 12<l, 11~12 C ORDt.(5') Otherwise res(1) --scope(l) = l (b) If k:sub(l~)E C~, then l'<k E ORDz and ORD~, c ORD~. (ii) A UDRS-clause is a pair (l:(~0, ...,'Yn), ORDt), where 7~ -~ (li:Ki,res(li),scope(li),ORDl,), 0 <_ i _< n, are UDRS components, and ORDl contains all of the conditions in (a) to (c) and an arbitrary subset oif those in (d) and (e). (a) ORDI, C ORDI, for all i, 0 < i < n (b) IQ<_scope(li) E ORDt for all i, 1 < i < n (c) li<<_l e ORDI for all i, 1 < i < n. (d) l~<_scope(lj) E ORDt, for some i,j 1 <_ i,j <_ n such that ORD is a partial order. For each i, 1 < i < n, li is called a node. I is called upper bound and/0 lower bound of the UDRS-clause. Lower bounds neither have distinguished conditions nor is there an/I such that l ~<l. (iii) A UDRS-database is a set of UDRSs ((/iT:F, ORDl~))i. A UDRS-goal is a UDRS. For the fragment of this paper UDRS-components that contain distinguished conditions do not contain anything else, i.e. they consist of labelled DRSs K for which UK = C~ = {) if C~: ~ {). We assume that semantic values of verbs are associated with lower bounds of UDRS-clauses and NP-meanings with their other components. Then the definition of UDRSs ensures that 5 (i) the verb is in the scope of each of its arguments, (clause (ii.b)), (ii) the scope of proper quantifiers is clause bounded, (clause (ii.c)) For relative clauses the upper bound label l ~ is subordinated to the label I of its head noun (i.e. the restrictor of the NP containing the relative) by l'<l(see (ii)). In the case of conditionals the upper bound label of subordinate clauses is set equal to the label of the antecedent/consequent of the implicative condition. The ordering of the set of labels of a UDRS builds an upper-semilattice with one-element IT. We assume that databases are constructed out of sequences $1, ..., S~ of sentences. Having a unique one-element /t r associated with each UDRS representing a sentence Si is to prevent any quantifier of Si to have scope over (parts of) any other sentence.",
"num": null,
"uris": null,
"type_str": "figure"
},
"FIGREF3": {
"text": "4Wedefinel<l' :=l<l IAl\u00a2l t. 5For the construction of underspecified representations see[2], this volume.",
"num": null,
"uris": null,
"type_str": "figure"
},
"FIGREF4": {
"text": "(i) if l:~(ll,12) occurs in K', then f(/)::=~(f(ll),f(12)), (ii) if l:-~ll occurs in K', then f(/):-~f(ll).For the formulation of the deduction rules it is convenient to introduce the following abbreviation. Let ]C be a UDRS and l some of its labels. Then ]Ct is the sub-UDRS of )~ dominated by l, i.e. Kz contains all conditions l':~ such that l'<_l and its ordering relation is the restriction of ]C's ordering relation. Suppose 7 = lo:ll==>12 is the distinguished condition of a UDRS component l:K occurring in a UDRS clause ]Ci of a UDRS K:. And suppose there is an embedding f of ]G1 into a set of conditions ?:5 of ]C such that l <: ?. Then the result of an application of DET to 7 is a clause ]~ that is obtained from ]Cl by (i) eliminating/C h from K:l (ii) replacing all occurrences of discourse referents in the remaining structure by new ones and the discourse referents x declared in the universe of/i, by f(x); (iii) substituting l' for l, /1, and /2 in ORDt; and (iv) replacing all other labels of K:l by new ones. But note that applications of DET are restricted to NPs that occur 'in the context of' implicative conditions, or monotone increasing quantifiers, as shown in (16). Suppose we know that John is a politician, then: (16)Few problems preoccupy every politician. t/Few problems preoccupy John. Every politician didn't sleep. ~/John didn't sleep. At least one problem preoccupies every pol.",
"num": null,
"uris": null,
"type_str": "figure"
},
"FIGREF5": {
"text": "Suppose l:K occurs in a UDRS clause (/0:(7o,...,Tn),ORDzo), where l0 has positive polarity, written lo +. Then l has positive (negative) polarity if for each disambiguation the cardinality of the set of monotone decreasing components (i.e. monotone decreasing quantifiers or negations) that takes wide scope over l is even (odd). Negative polarity of l0 is induces the complementary distribution of polarity marking for l. If l is the label of a complex condition, then the polarity of l determines the polarity of the arguments of this condition according to the following patterns: l+:l-~, l-:~12-, /+ :-~, and l-:-~, l~ has positive polarity for every i. The polarity of the upper bound label of a UDRSclause is inherited from the polarity of the label the UDRS-clause is attached to. Verbs, i.e. lower bounds of UDRS-clauses, always have definite polarities if the upper bound label of the same clause has. Two remarks are in order before we come to the formulation of DET. First, the polarity distribution can be done without explicitly calculating all disambi-guations. The label l of a component l:K is positive (negative) in the clause in which occurs, if the set of components on the path to the upper bound label l + of this clause contains an even (odd) number of polarity changing elements, and all other components of the clause (i.e. those occurring on other paths) do not change polarity. Second, the fragment of UDRSs we are considering in this paper does not contain a treatment of n-ary quantifiers. Especially we do not deal with resumptive quantifiers, like <no boy, no girl> in No boy likes no girl. If we do not consider the fact that this sentence may be read as No boy likes any girl the polarity marking defined above will mark the label of the verb as positive. But if we take this reading into account, i.e. allow to construe the two quantified NPs as constituents of the resumptive quantifier, then one negation is cancelled and the label of the verb cannot get a definite value. 7 To represent DET schematically we write (IT:a(F:7),ORD) to indicate that i~:K is a component of the UDRS K:IT with polarity 7r and distinguished condition 7. A (lT:a(~:~ ~ ~),ORD) f:/Q,, ~-+ A exists",
"num": null,
"uris": null,
"type_str": "figure"
},
"FIGREF6": {
"text": "IT : (14 : X snore , 15 : ~-~P-~, ORD)",
"num": null,
"uris": null,
"type_str": "figure"
},
"FIGREF7": {
"text": "ll, 12}>>(Q, l~, l~) if Q is persistent and A K1Q1 >>Etl ,or A K (-%/Q1,/CI~ } (Q, ll, 12)>>(Q, l~, l~) if Q is anti-pers, and A ~-]Ct~ >2> ]Cll, or 9f(7) is 7 with discourse referents x occurring in 7 replaced by f(z).",
"num": null,
"uris": null,
"type_str": "figure"
},
"FIGREF8": {
"text": "A }-{-~,]qi,~,,) >> -~-A }-{-~,/i)>>{-~,/~) if 1. A ~-Kq >> Kt,, or 2. A ~-(--+, ~2~;, K,,)",
"num": null,
"uris": null,
"type_str": "figure"
},
"TABREF1": {
"text": "is already the UDRS that represents (10) with scope relationships left unresolved. We call the nodes of such graphs UDRS-components. Each UDRScomponent consists of a labelled DRS and two functions scope and res, which map labels of UDRScomponents to the labels of their scope and restrictor, respectively. DRS-conditions are of the form (Q, l~1, l~2), with quantifier Q, restrictor//1 and scope li2, of the form lil~li2, or of the form li:-~lil. A UDRS is a set of UDRS-components together with a partial order ORD of its labels. If we make (some) labels explicit we may represent (14) as in (15). If ORD in (15) is given as {12 <_ scope(ll),13 <_ scope(12)} then (15) is equivalent to (11), and in case ORD is {11 _< scope(12), 13 <_ scope(ll)} we get a description of (12). If ORD is {13 _< scope(ll), 13 <_ scope(12)} then (15) represents",
"content": "<table><tr><td>(13) 1 hum:n(x) I=\u00a2~J</td><td/></tr><tr><td>Ix pay attention]</td><td>Ix pay attention 1</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">Having achieved this separation we are able to re-</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">present the structure that is common to both, (11)</td></tr><tr><td>and (12), by (14).</td><td/></tr><tr><td>human(x) =~</td><td/></tr><tr><td/><td>Ix ~)ay att. I</td></tr><tr><td>(14)</td><td/></tr></table>",
"html": null,
"type_str": "table",
"num": null
},
"TABREF2": {
"text": "ORIY' results from ORIY by replacing 16 and scope(16) with l~-. RAA is now applicable to the new goal in a standard way. It should be clear, however, that the order of application we have cho-sen, i.e. COND before RAA, results in having given the universal quantifier wide scope over the negation. This means that after having applied COND we are not in the process of proving the original ambiguous goal any more. What we are going to prove instead is that reading of the goal with universal quantifier having wide scope over the negation.",
"content": "<table><tr><td/><td>Be-</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">ginning with RAA instead of COND assigns the ne-</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">gation wide scope over the quantifier, as we would</td></tr><tr><td>add (l~r:(l~:[~ ~ ~, Is:~),ORD\")to</td><td>the</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">data in order to derive a contradiction, s Here ORlY'</td></tr><tr><td colspan=\"2\">results from ORU by replacing 17 and scope(17) with l~-.</td></tr><tr><td/><td colspan=\"2\">An application of COND to the goal in (18) results</td></tr><tr><td/><td colspan=\"2\">in adding &lt;IT:] a I, { }) to the data and leaves</td></tr><tr><td/><td>(/tc:(lT:q q ,ls:~</td><td>}, ORD\" ) to be shown, whe-</td></tr></table>",
"html": null,
"type_str": "table",
"num": null
},
"TABREF3": {
"text": "Let 7r be the relation between quantifiers that allows neigbourhood exchanges, i.e. 7~ ~ V2 iff ]Q, ~-]C~,, where/C~, results from ]Q1 by exchanging 71 and V2, i.e. by replacing 12 <i scope(f1) in /Ch's ORD by 11 <i scope(12).",
"content": "<table><tr><td>every, 11,12&gt;&gt;&gt;(more than half, 11,12&gt;</td></tr><tr><td>(ii) (every, ll, 12)&gt;&gt;({}, {Mary}, 12}</td></tr><tr><td>(iii) (no, ll, 12)&gt;&gt;(every, 11, I~2:-~12)</td></tr><tr><td>(iv) (some, 11, ll2:-,12)&gt;&gt;(not every, 11,/2)</td></tr><tr><td>(v) snore&gt;&gt;sleep if }_z: snore&gt;&gt;sleep</td></tr><tr><td>The last rule allows relative scopes of quantifiers to</td></tr><tr><td>be inverted.</td></tr><tr><td>&gt;&gt; 7r:</td></tr><tr><td>(i) Let ~ :~/1 and 12 :V2 be two quantifiers of a UDRS</td></tr><tr><td>]C such that 11 immediately dominates /2 (/2 _&lt;i</td></tr><tr><td>scope(f1)). Then</td></tr><tr><td>A }-/C h &gt;&gt; /CI, if 11:71 7r 4:72 and 11:71 ~r l':~/' for</td></tr><tr><td>all l' :V ~ that may be immediately dominated by/1 :V1</td></tr><tr><td>(in any disambiguation).</td></tr><tr><td>(ii) Analoguously for the case of 1/7:71 having nega-</td></tr><tr><td>tive polarity.</td></tr></table>",
"html": null,
"type_str": "table",
"num": null
}
}
}
}