|
{ |
|
"paper_id": "E99-1006", |
|
"header": { |
|
"generated_with": "S2ORC 1.0.0", |
|
"date_generated": "2023-01-19T10:37:24.232522Z" |
|
}, |
|
"title": "Resolving Discourse Deictic Anaphora in Dialogues", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Miriam", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Eckert", |
|
"suffix": "", |
|
"affiliation": { |
|
"laboratory": "", |
|
"institution": "Cognitive Science University of Pennsylvania", |
|
"location": { |
|
"addrLine": "3401 Walnut Street, Suite 400A Philadelphia", |
|
"postCode": "19104", |
|
"region": "PA", |
|
"country": "USA" |
|
} |
|
}, |
|
"email": "miriame@edu" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Michael", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Strube", |
|
"suffix": "", |
|
"affiliation": { |
|
"laboratory": "", |
|
"institution": "Cognitive Science University of Pennsylvania", |
|
"location": { |
|
"addrLine": "3401 Walnut Street, Suite 400A Philadelphia", |
|
"postCode": "19104", |
|
"region": "PA", |
|
"country": "USA" |
|
} |
|
}, |
|
"email": "strube@linc@edu" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": "", |
|
"venue": null, |
|
"identifiers": {}, |
|
"abstract": "Most existing anaphora resolution algorithms are designed to account only for anaphors with NP-antecedents. This paper describes an algorithm for the resolution of discourse deictic anaphors, which constitute a large percentage of anaphors in spoken dialogues. The success of the resolution is dependent on the classification of all pronouns and demonstratives into individual, discourse deictic and vague anaphora. Finally, the empirical results of the application of the algorithm to a corpus of spoken dialogues are presented.", |
|
"pdf_parse": { |
|
"paper_id": "E99-1006", |
|
"_pdf_hash": "", |
|
"abstract": [ |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Most existing anaphora resolution algorithms are designed to account only for anaphors with NP-antecedents. This paper describes an algorithm for the resolution of discourse deictic anaphors, which constitute a large percentage of anaphors in spoken dialogues. The success of the resolution is dependent on the classification of all pronouns and demonstratives into individual, discourse deictic and vague anaphora. Finally, the empirical results of the application of the algorithm to a corpus of spoken dialogues are presented.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Abstract", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"body_text": [ |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Most anaphora resolution algorithms are designed to deal with the co-indexing relation between anaphors and NP-antecedents. In the spoken language corpus we examined -the Switchboard corpus of telephone conversations (LDC, 1993 ) -this type of link only accounts for 45.1% of all anaphoric references. Another 22.6% are anaphors whose referents are not individual, concrete entities but events, facts and propositions, e.g.,", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 217, |
|
"end": 227, |
|
"text": "(LDC, 1993", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "(1) B.7:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "A.8: [ We never know what they're thinking]/. Thati's right. [I don't trust them]j, maybe I guess itj's because of what happened over there with their own people, how they threw them out of power. (sw3241)", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 5, |
|
"end": 6, |
|
"text": "[", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Whilst there have been attempts to classify abstract objects and the rules governing anaphoric reference to them (Webber, 1991; Asher, 1993; Dahl and Hellman, 1995) , there have been no exhaustive, empirical studies using actual resolution algorithms. These have so far only been applied to written corpora. However, the high frequency of abstract object anaphora in dialogues means that any attempt to resolve anaphors in spoken language cannot succeed without taking this into account.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 113, |
|
"end": 127, |
|
"text": "(Webber, 1991;", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF19" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 128, |
|
"end": 140, |
|
"text": "Asher, 1993;", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF0" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 141, |
|
"end": 164, |
|
"text": "Dahl and Hellman, 1995)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF7" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Summarised below are some issues specific to anaphora resolution in spoken dialogues (see also Byron and Stent (1998) who mention some of these problems in their account of the Centering model (Grosz et al., 1995) ).", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 95, |
|
"end": 117, |
|
"text": "Byron and Stent (1998)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 193, |
|
"end": 213, |
|
"text": "(Grosz et al., 1995)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF9" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Center of attention in multi-party discourse. In spontaneous speech it is possible that the participants of a dialogue may not be focussing on the same entity at a given point in the discourse.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Utterances with no discourse entities. E.g., Uhhuh; yeah; right. Byron and Stent (1998) and Walker (1998) assign no importance to such utterances in their models. We assume that these also can be used to acknowledge a preceding utterance.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 65, |
|
"end": 87, |
|
"text": "Byron and Stent (1998)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 92, |
|
"end": 105, |
|
"text": "Walker (1998)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF18" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Abandoned or partial utterances. Speakers may interrupt each other or make speech repairs, e.g.,", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "(2) Uh, our son/has this kind of, you know, he/'s, well hei started out going Stephen F Austin (sw3117)", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Self-corrected speech cannot be ignored as can be seen by the fact that the entity referred to by the NP our son is subsequently referred to by a pronoun and must therefore have entered the discourse model.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Introduction", |
|
"sec_num": "1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Most anaphor resolution algorithms rely on a syntactic definition of utterance which cannot be provided by spoken dialogue as there is no punctuation to mark complete sentences.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Determination of utterance boundaries.", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "These issues are dealt with by our method of segmenting dialogues into dialogue acts with specified discourse functions. In addition, our approach presents a simple classification of individual and abstract object anaphors and uses separate algorithms for each class. We build on the recall rate of state-of-the-art pronoun resolution algorithms but we achieve a far higher precision than would be achieved by applying these to spoken language because the classification of anaphors prevents the algorithm from co-indexing discourse deictic anaphora with individual antecedents.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Determination of utterance boundaries.", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Section 2 gives definitions and frequency of occurrence of the different anaphor types. Section 3 describes the segmentation of the dialogues into dialogue acts and the influence of these on the entities in the discourse model. Section 4 presents the method we use for resolving anaphors and the corresponding algorithm. In Section 5, we report on the corpus annotation and the evaluation of the algorithm.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Determination of utterance boundaries.", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "In the dialogues examined, only 45.1% of the anaphors are individual anaphors, i.e., anaphors with NPantecedents (IPro, IDem), e.g.,", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Anaphor Types in Dialogues", |
|
"sec_num": "2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "(3) Boeing ought to hire himi and give him/ a junkyardj .... and see if hei could build a Seven Forty-Seven out of itj. sw210222.6% of the anaphors are discourse deictic, i.e. co-specify with non-NP constituents such as VPs, sentences, strings of sentences (DDPro, DDDem; cf. Webber (1991) ). The phenomenon of discourse deictic anaphora in written texts has been shown to be strongly dependent on discourse structure. As can also be seen in the examples below, anaphoric reference is restricted to elements adjacent to the utterance containing the anaphor, i.e., those on the right frontier of the discourse structure tree (Webber, 1991; Asher, 1993) :", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 276, |
|
"end": 289, |
|
"text": "Webber (1991)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF19" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 624, |
|
"end": 638, |
|
"text": "(Webber, 1991;", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF19" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 639, |
|
"end": 651, |
|
"text": "Asher, 1993)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF0" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Anaphor Types in Dialogues", |
|
"sec_num": "2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "(4) A.46: [The government don't tell you", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Anaphor Types in Dialogues", |
|
"sec_num": "2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "everything.]i B.47: I knowit/ (sw3241) (5) Now why didn't she [take him over there with her]i? No, she didn't do thati.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Anaphor Types in Dialogues", |
|
"sec_num": "2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The existence of abstract object anaphora shows that aside from individual entities, the discourse model may also contain complex, higher-order entities. One of the differences between individual and discourse deictic anaphora is that whereas a concrete NP antecedent usually only refers to the individual it describes, a sentence may simultaneously denote an eventuality, a concept, a proposition and a fact.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "(sw4877)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Instead of assuming that all levels of abstract objects are introduced to the discourse model by the sentence that makes them available, it has been suggested that anaphoric discourse deictic reference involves referent coercion (Webber, 1991; Asher, 1993; Dahl and Hellman, 1995) . This assumption is further justified by the fact that discourse deictic reference, as opposed to individual anaphoric reference, is often established by demonstratives rather than pronouns. In theories relating cognitive status and choice of NP-form (cf. Gundel et al. (1993) ), pronouns are only available for the most salient entities, whereas demonstratives can be used to shift the focus of attention to a different entity.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 229, |
|
"end": 243, |
|
"text": "(Webber, 1991;", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF19" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 244, |
|
"end": 256, |
|
"text": "Asher, 1993;", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF0" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 257, |
|
"end": 280, |
|
"text": "Dahl and Hellman, 1995)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF7" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 538, |
|
"end": 558, |
|
"text": "Gundel et al. (1993)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF10" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "(sw4877)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "A further 19.1% of anaphors are Inferrable-Evoked Pronouns (IEPro) and constitute a particular type of plural pronoun which indirectly co-specifies with a singular antecedent. This group includes existential, generic and corporate 3rd person plural pronouns (Jaeggli, 1986; Belletti and Rizzi, 1988 ).", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 258, |
|
"end": 273, |
|
"text": "(Jaeggli, 1986;", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF11" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 274, |
|
"end": 298, |
|
"text": "Belletti and Rizzi, 1988", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF1" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "(sw4877)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "(6) I think the Soviet Union knows what we have and knows that we're pretty serious and if they ever tried to do anything, we would, we would be on the offensive. sw3241In (6), the NP Soviet Union can be associated with inferrables such as the population or the government.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "(sw4877)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "These can subsequently be referred to by pronouns without having been explicitly mentioned themselves. In some cases of IEPro's there is no associated NP, as in the following example, where the speaker is referring to the organisers of the Switchboard calls:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "(sw4877)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "(7) this is the first call I've done [...] and, I didn't realize that they ha-, were going to reach out to people from [...] all over the country.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 37, |
|
"end": 42, |
|
"text": "[...]", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 119, |
|
"end": 124, |
|
"text": "[...]", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "(sw4877)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "13.2% of the anaphors are vague (VagPro, Vag-Dem), in the sense that they refer to the general topic of conversation and, as opposed to discourse deictic anaphors, do not have a specific clause as an antecedent, e.g., (8) B.29: I mean, the baby is like seventeen months and she just screams. A.30: Uh-huh. B.31 : Well even if she knows that they're fixing to get ready to go over there. They're not even there yet -A.32: Uh-huh. B.33: -you know. A.34: Yeah. It's hard.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "(sw4877)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Non-referring pronouns, or expletives, were not marked. These include subjects of weather verbs, those in raising verb constructions or those occurring in sentences with extraposed sentential subjects or objects, e.g., (9) It's hard to realize, that there are places that are just so, uh, bare on the shelves as there.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "(sw4877)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "This group also contains the various subcategorised expletives (Postal and Pullum, 1988) , defined as being non-referring pronouns in argument positions, e.g., (10) Uh, they don't need somebody else coming in and saying, you know, okay we're going to be with them and we're going to zap it to you. (sw2403) (11) When it comes to trucks, though, I would probably think to go American. sw2326They differ from referring anaphors in that they cannot be questioned (e.g., *When what comes to trucks ?).", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 63, |
|
"end": 88, |
|
"text": "(Postal and Pullum, 1988)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF15" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "(sw4877)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The domain which contains potential antecedents is not given in syntactic terms in spoken dialogue. Hence we define this domain in pragmatic terms. We assume that discourse entities enter the joint discourse model and are available for subsequent reference when common ground between the discourse participants is established. Our model builds on the observation that certain dialogue acts -in particular acknowledgments signal that common ground is achieved. Our assumptions are based on Clark's (1989) theory of contributions (cf. also Traum (1994)).", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Synchronising Units", |
|
"sec_num": "3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Each dialogue is divided into short, clearly defined dialogue acts -Initiations I and Acknowledgments A -based on the top of the hierarchy given in Carletta et al. (1997) . Each sentence and each conjoined clause counts as a separate I, even if they are part of the same turn. A's do not convey semantic content but have a pragmatic function (e.g., backchannel). In addition there are utterances which function as an A but also have semantic content -these are labelled as A/I.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 148, |
|
"end": 170, |
|
"text": "Carletta et al. (1997)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Synchronising Units", |
|
"sec_num": "3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "A single I is paired with an A and they jointly form a Synchronising Unit (SU). In longer turns, each main clause functions as a separate unit along with its subordinate clauses. Single I's constitute SU's by themselves and do not require explicit acknowledgment.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Synchronising Units", |
|
"sec_num": "3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The assumption is that by letting the speaker continue, the hearer implicitly acknowledges the utterance. It is only in the context of turn-taking that I's and A's are paired up. Our model is based on the observation that common ground has an influence on attentional state. We assume that only entities in a complete SU are entered into the common ground and remain in the Slist for the duration of a further SU. If one speaker's I is not acknowledged by the other participant it cannot be included in an SU. In this case the discourse entities mentioned in the unacknowledged I are added to the S-List but are immediately deleted again when the subsequent I clearly shows that they are not part of the common ground. Speaker u's second turn is an I which is not followed by an A. This means that the entity referred to in that utterance (orange warehouse) is immediately removed from the joint discourse model. Thus there in the final two turns co-specifies with Coming and not the most recent orange warehouse.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Synchronising Units", |
|
"sec_num": "3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We now turn to our method of anaphora resolution, which extends the algorithm presented in Strube (1998) , in order to be able to account for discourse deictic anaphora as well as individual anaphora.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 91, |
|
"end": 104, |
|
"text": "Strube (1998)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF16" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "How to Resolve Discourse Deictic Anaphora", |
|
"sec_num": "4" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "As indicated in Section 2, information provided by the subcategorisation frame of the anaphor's predicate can be used to determine the type of the referent. In the algorithm, we make use of the notion of anaphorantecedent Compatibility to distinguish between discourse deictic and individual reference. Certain predicates (notably verbs of propositional attitude) require one of their arguments to have a referent whose meaning is correlated with sentences, e.g., is true, assume (referred to as SC-bias verbs in Garnsey et al. (1997) and elsewhere). Pronouns in these positions rarely have concrete individual NP-antecedents and are generally only compatible with discourse deictic referents. Other argument positions are preferentially associated with concrete individuals (e.g., objects of eat, smell) (DO-bias verbs) . A summary of these predicate types is provided in Figure 2 , where l-incompatible", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 513, |
|
"end": 534, |
|
"text": "Garnsey et al. (1997)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF8" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 805, |
|
"end": 820, |
|
"text": "(DO-bias verbs)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 873, |
|
"end": 881, |
|
"text": "Figure 2", |
|
"ref_id": "FIGREF1" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Anaphor-anteeedent Compatibility", |
|
"sec_num": "4.1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Equating constructions where a pronominal referent is equated with an abstract object, e.g., x is making it easy, x is a suggestion.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I-Incompatible (*I)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Copula constructions whose adjectives can only be applied to abstract entities, e.g., x is true, x is false,", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I-Incompatible (*I)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "x is correct, x is right, x isn't right.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I-Incompatible (*I)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "\u2022 Arguments of verbs describing propositional attitude which only take S'-complements, e.g., assume.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I-Incompatible (*I)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "\u2022 Object of do.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I-Incompatible (*I)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "\u2022 Predicate or anaphoric referent is a \"reason\", e.g., x", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I-Incompatible (*I)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "is because I like her, x is why he ' s late.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "I-Incompatible (*I)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Equating constructions where a pronominal referent is equated with a concrete individual referent, e.g., x", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "A-Incompatible (*A)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "is a car.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "A-Incompatible (*A)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Copula constructions whose adjectives can only be applied to concrete entities, e.g., x is expensive, x is tasty, x is loud.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "A-Incompatible (*A)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Arguments of verbs describing physical contact/stimulation, which cannot be used metaphorically, e.g., break x, smash x, eat x, drink x, smell x but NOT *see x It is clear that predicate information alone is not sufficient for this purpose as there is a large group of verbs which allow both individual and discourse deictic referents (e.g., objects of see, know) (EQ-bias verbs) . In these cases the preference is determined by NP-form of the anaphor (pronoun vs. demonstrative).", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 364, |
|
"end": 379, |
|
"text": "(EQ-bias verbs)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "A-Incompatible (*A)", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We follow Asher (1993) in assuming that the predicate of a discourse deictic anaphor determines the type of abstract object. An anaphor in the object position of the verb do, for example, can only have a VP (eventconcept) antecedent (eg John [sang] . Bill did that too.), whereas an anaphor in the subject position of the predicate is true requires a full S (proposition) (eg [John sang]. That's true.). This verbal subcategorisation information is used to determine which part of the preceding I is required to form the correct referent.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 10, |
|
"end": 22, |
|
"text": "Asher (1993)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF0" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 242, |
|
"end": 248, |
|
"text": "[sang]", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Types of Abstract Antecedents", |
|
"sec_num": "4.2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Following Webber and others, we assume that an abstract object is only introduced to the discourse model by the anaphor itself. In addition to the S-List (Strube, 1998) , which contains the referents of NPs available for anaphoric reference, our model includes ~These are preferences and not strict rules because some l-Incompatible contexts are compatible with NPs denoting abstract objects, e.g., The story/It is true. and NPs which are used to stand elliptically for an event or state, e.g., His car/It is the reason why he's late. This shows that predicate compatibility must ultimately be defined in semantic terms and not just rely on syntactic strings (NP vs. S).", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 154, |
|
"end": 168, |
|
"text": "(Strube, 1998)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF16" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Types of Abstract Antecedents", |
|
"sec_num": "4.2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "an A-List for abstract objects. This is only filled if discourse deictic pronouns or demonstratives occur and its contents remain only for one I, which is necessary for multiple discourse deictic reference to the same entity.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Types of Abstract Antecedents", |
|
"sec_num": "4.2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The following context ranking describes the order in which the parts of the linguistic context are accessed: 1. A-List (containing abstract objects previously referred to anaphorically).", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Types of Abstract Antecedents", |
|
"sec_num": "4.2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "2. Within same I: Clause to the left of the clause containing the anaphor.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Types of Abstract Antecedents", |
|
"sec_num": "4.2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "3. Within previous I: Rightmost main clause (and subordinated clauses to its right).", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Types of Abstract Antecedents", |
|
"sec_num": "4.2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "4. Within previous rs: Rightmost complete sentence (if previous I is incomplete sentence). ", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Types of Abstract Antecedents", |
|
"sec_num": "4.2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The algorithm consists of two branches, one for the resolution of pronouns, the other for the resolution of demonstratives. Both of them call the functions re-solveDD and resolvelnd, which resolve discourse deictic anaphora and individual anaphora, respectively. If a pronoun is encountered (Figure 4, below) , the functions resolveDD or resolvelnd (described below) are evaluated, depending on whether the pronoun is Iincompatible (1) or A-incompatible (2). In the case of success the pronouns are classified as DDPro or lPro, respectively. In the case of failure, the pronouns are classified as VagPro. If the pronoun is neither I-nor A-incompatible (i.e., the pronoun is ambiguous in this respect), the classification is only dependent on the If successful, the pronoun is classified as IPro, if unsuccessful, the function resolveDD attempts to resolve the pronoun (4). If this, in turn, is successful, the pronoun is classified as DDPro, if it is unsuccessful it is classified as VagPro, indicating that the pronoun cannot be resolved using the linguistic context. The procedure is similar in the case of demonstrafives ( Figure 5, below) . The only difference being that the antecedent of a demonstrative is preferentially an abstract object. The order of (3) and (4) is therefore reversed.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 291, |
|
"end": 308, |
|
"text": "(Figure 4, below)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 1126, |
|
"end": 1142, |
|
"text": "Figure 5, below)", |
|
"ref_id": "FIGREF3" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "The Algorithm", |
|
"sec_num": "4.3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We now turn to the function resolveDD ( Figure 6 , below) (assuming that resolvelnd resolves individual anaphora and returns true or false depending on its success). In step (1) the function resolveDD examines all elements of the context ranking (Figure 3) until the function co-index succeeds, which evaluates whether the element is of the right type. Then the function resolveDD returns true. If the pronoun is an argument of \"do\", the function co-index is tried on the VP of the current element of the context ranking (2). If successful, the VP-referent is added to the A-List and the function returns true. In (3), co-index evaluates whether the pronoun and the current element of the context ranking are compatible. In the case of a positive result, the element is added to the A-List and true is returned. If all elements of the context ranking are resolveDD(PRO) := 1. foreach element of context ranking do 2.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 40, |
|
"end": 48, |
|
"text": "Figure 6", |
|
"ref_id": "FIGREF4" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 246, |
|
"end": 256, |
|
"text": "(Figure 3)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "The Algorithm", |
|
"sec_num": "4.3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "if (PRO is argument of do) then if (co-index PRO with VP of element) then add VP to A-List; return true 3.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "The Algorithm", |
|
"sec_num": "4.3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "else if (co-index PRO with element) then add element to A-List; return true 4. return false. Example 12 illustrates the algorithm:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "The Algorithm", |
|
"sec_num": "4.3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "(12) B.8: I mean, if went and policed, just like you say, every country when they had squabbles, A.9: Well, but we've done it before, B.10: Oh, I know we have. A. 11 : and it has not been successful. (sw2403) When the pronoun \"it\" in A.9 is encountered, the algorithm determines the pronoun to be Iincompatible (Step 1 in Figure 4) , as it is the object argument of the verb do. The function resolveDD is evaluated. The A-List is empty, so the highest ranked element in the context ranking is the last complete sentence in B.8. The pronoun is an argument of \"do\", therefore gets co-indexed with the VP-referent of the sentence in B.8. The VP is added to the A-List, the function returns true and the pronoun is classified as DDPro by the algorithm.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 322, |
|
"end": 331, |
|
"text": "Figure 4)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "The Algorithm", |
|
"sec_num": "4.3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "When the next pronoun is encountered, the A-List is empty again because of the intervening sentence (I) in B.10. The pronoun is neither I-nor A-incompatible, therefore the algorithm evaluates resolvelnd (step 3). This fails, since there are no individual antecedents available in B. 10 and the algorithm evaluates resolveDD in the step (4). The first element in the context ranking is the main clause in A. 11 which is co-indexed with the pronoun. The clause-referent is added to the A-List, the function returns true and the algorithm classifies the pronoun as DDPro. In this case, the classification is correct but not the resolution, since the pronoun should co-specify with the pronoun in A.9.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "The Algorithm", |
|
"sec_num": "4.3" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "In order to test the hypotheses made in the previous sections we performed an empirical evaluation on nat-urally occurring dialogues. First, the corpus was annotated for all relevant features, i.e., division of turns into dialogue act units, classification of dialogue acts (I, A), marking of noun phrases, classification of the various types of anaphors introduced in Section 2, and annotating coreference between anaphors and individual/abstract discourse entities. The last step provided the key for the test of the algorithm described in Section 4.3.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Empirical Evaluation", |
|
"sec_num": "5" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Our data consisted of five randomly selected dialogues from the Switchboard corpus of spoken telephone conversations (LDC, 1993) . Two dialogues (SW2041, SW4877) were used to train the two annotators (the authors), and three further dialogues for testing (SW2403, SW3117, SW3241). The training dialogues were used for improving the annotation manual and for clarifying the annotation in borderline cases. After each step the annotations were compared using the ~ statistic as reliability measure for all classification tasks (Carletta, 1996) . A t~ of 0.68 < ~ < 0.80 allows tentative conclusions while ~ > 0.80 indicates reliability between the annotators. In the following tables, the rows on above the horizontal line show how often a particular class was actually marked as such by both annotators. In the rows below the line, N shows the total number of markables, while Z gives the number of agreements between the annotations. PA is percent agreement between the annotators, PE expected agreement by chance. Finally, ~ is computed by the formula PA -PE/1 -PE.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 117, |
|
"end": 128, |
|
"text": "(LDC, 1993)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 525, |
|
"end": 541, |
|
"text": "(Carletta, 1996)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF4" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Annotation", |
|
"sec_num": "5.1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Dialogue Acts. First, turns were segmented into dialogue act units. We turned the segmentation task into a classification task by using boundaries between dialogue acts as one class and non-boundaries as the other (see Passonneau and Litman (1997) for a similar practice). In Table l , Non-Bound. and Bound. give the number of non-boundaries and boundaries actually marked by the annotators, N is the total number of possible boundary sites, while Z gives the number of agreements between the annotations. Table 2 shows the results of the comparison between the annotations with respect to the classification of the dialogue act units into Initiations (I), Acknowledgements (A), Acknowledgement/Initiations (A/I), and no dialogue act (No) . For this test we used only these dialogue act units which the annotators agreed about. PA was 92.6%, ~ = 0.87 again indicating that it is possible to annotate these classes reliably. Co-Indexation of Abstract Object Anaphora. The abstract object anaphora were manually co-indexed 2No. for each class is the actual no. marked by both annotators. N is the total number of markables, Z is total number of agreements between annotators, PE is the expected agreement by chance.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 219, |
|
"end": 247, |
|
"text": "Passonneau and Litman (1997)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF14" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 734, |
|
"end": 738, |
|
"text": "(No)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 276, |
|
"end": 283, |
|
"text": "Table l", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 506, |
|
"end": 513, |
|
"text": "Table 2", |
|
"ref_id": "TABREF4" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Annotation", |
|
"sec_num": "5.1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "with their antecedents. For this task we cannot provide reliability scores using n because it is not a classification task. It is much more difficult than the previous ones, as the problem consists of identifying the correct beginning and end of the string which cospecifies with the anaphor. We used only the abstract anaphors whose classification both annotators agreed upon. The annotators then marked the antecedents and co-indexed them with the anaphors. The results were compared and the annotators agreed upon a reconciled version of the data. Annotator accuracy was then measured against the reconciled version. Accuracy ranged from 85,7% (Annotator A) to 94,3% (Annotator B). ", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Annotation", |
|
"sec_num": "5.1" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We used the reconciled version of the annotation as key for the abstract anaphora resolution algorithm. Ta The low value for precision indicates that the classification did not perform very well. Of the 28 anaphors resolved incorrectly, only 11 were classified correctly. One of the most common errors in classification was, that an anaphor annotated as vague (VagPro, VagDem) was classified by the algorithm as discourse deictic (DDPro, DDDem) . Classification is dependent on resolution, so since the context almost always provides an antecedent for a discourse deictic anaphor, it is possible to classify and resolve a vague anaphor incorrectly, as in Example 13: (13) A: [I don't know]/ , I think it/ really depends a lot on the child. (sw3117)", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 360, |
|
"end": 376, |
|
"text": "(VagPro, VagDem)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 430, |
|
"end": 444, |
|
"text": "(DDPro, DDDem)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 104, |
|
"end": 106, |
|
"text": "Ta", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Evaluation of the Algorithm", |
|
"sec_num": "5.2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Both Webber(1991) and Asher (1993) describe the phenomenon of abstract object anaphora and present restrictions on the set of potential antecedents. They do not, however, concern themselves with the problem of how to classify a certain pronoun or demonstrative as individual or abstract. Also, as they do not give preferences on the set of potential candidates, their approaches are not intended as attempts to resolve abstract object anaphora. Concerning anaphora resolution in dialogues, only little research has been carried out in this area to our knowledge. LuperFoy (1992) does not present a corpus study, meaning that statistics about the distribution of individual and abstract object anaphora or about the success rate of her approach are not available. Byron and Stent (1998) present extensions of the centering model (Grosz et al., 1995) for spoken dialogue and identify several problems with the model. We have chosen Strube's (1998) model for the resolution of individual anaphora as basis because it avoids the problems encountered by Byron & Stent, who also do not present data on the resolution of pronouns in dialogues and do not mention abstract object anaphora. Dagan and Itai (1991) describe a corpus-based approach to the resolution of pronouns, which is evaluated for the neuter pronoun \"it\". Again, abstract object anaphora are not mentioned.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 5, |
|
"end": 17, |
|
"text": "Webber(1991)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF19" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 22, |
|
"end": 34, |
|
"text": "Asher (1993)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF0" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 763, |
|
"end": 785, |
|
"text": "Byron and Stent (1998)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF2" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 828, |
|
"end": 848, |
|
"text": "(Grosz et al., 1995)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF9" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 930, |
|
"end": 945, |
|
"text": "Strube's (1998)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF16" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 1181, |
|
"end": 1202, |
|
"text": "Dagan and Itai (1991)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF6" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Comparison to Related Work", |
|
"sec_num": "6" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "In this paper we presented a method for resolving abstract object anaphora in spoken language. We consider our approach to be a first step towards the unconstrained resolution of anaphora in dialogue.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusions and Future Work", |
|
"sec_num": "7" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The results of our method show that the recall is fairly high while the precision is relatively low. This indicates that the anaphor classification requires improvement, in particular the notion of Compatibility.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusions and Future Work", |
|
"sec_num": "7" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Lists of verb biases for sentential and NP complements, as described in psycholinguistic studies (e.g. Garnsey et al. (1997) ), could be used to classify verbs. Currently exisiting lists only account for a small number of verbs but there may be the possibility of adding statistical information from large corpora of spoken dialogue.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 103, |
|
"end": 124, |
|
"text": "Garnsey et al. (1997)", |
|
"ref_id": "BIBREF8" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusions and Future Work", |
|
"sec_num": "7" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Furthermore, the algorithm currently ignores abstract NPs (e.g., story, exercising) when looking for antecedents for anaphors with 1-incompatible predicates. We are considering determining the feature abstract for all NPs in order to identify those which can act as antecedents in such contexts. Information such as this could be used by the algorithm to prevent the anaphor classification from being dependent on anaphor resolution.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Conclusions and Future Work", |
|
"sec_num": "7" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"back_matter": [ |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Acknowledgments. We would like to thank Donna Byron and Amanda Stent for discussing the central issues contained in this paper. We are grateful to audiences at AT&T Labs-Research, the University of Delaware, IBM Research and the participants of Ellen Prince's Discourse Analysis Seminar for the critical feedback they provided. Thanks also to Jonathan De-Cristofaro and Kathleen E McCoy who discussed the empirical issues. Both authors are funded by postdoctoral fellowship awards from IRCS.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "acknowledgement", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"bib_entries": { |
|
"BIBREF0": { |
|
"ref_id": "b0", |
|
"title": "Reference to Abstract Objects", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Nicholas", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Asher", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1993, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Nicholas Asher. 1993. Reference to Abstract Objects. Kluwer, Dordrecht.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF1": { |
|
"ref_id": "b1", |
|
"title": "Psych verbs and theta theory. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Adriana", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Belletti", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Luigi", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Rizzi", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1988, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "6", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "291--352", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Adriana Belletti and Luigi Rizzi. 1988. Psych verbs and theta theory. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 6:291-352.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF2": { |
|
"ref_id": "b2", |
|
"title": "A preliminary model of centering in dialog", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Donna", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Byron", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Amanda", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Stent", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1998, |
|
"venue": "Proceedings of the 17 th International Conference on Computational Linguistics and 36 th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "1475--1477", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Donna Byron and Amanda Stent. 1998. A prelim- inary model of centering in dialog. In Proceed- ings of the 17 th International Conference on Com- putational Linguistics and 36 th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics, Montrral, Qurbec, Canada, 10-14 August 1998, pages 1475-1477.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF3": { |
|
"ref_id": "b3", |
|
"title": "Gwyneth Doherty-Sneddon, and Anne Anderson. 1997. The reliability of a dialogue structure coding scheme", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Jean", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Carletta", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Amy", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Isard", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Stephen", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Isard", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Jacqueline", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Kowtko", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": null, |
|
"venue": "Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "23", |
|
"issue": "1", |
|
"pages": "13--31", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Jean Carletta, Amy Isard, Stephen Isard, Jacqueline Kowtko, Gwyneth Doherty-Sneddon, and Anne An- derson. 1997. The reliability of a dialogue struc- ture coding scheme. Computational Linguistics, 23(1):13-31.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF4": { |
|
"ref_id": "b4", |
|
"title": "Assessing agreement on classification tasks: The kappa statistic", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Jean", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Carletta", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1996, |
|
"venue": "Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "22", |
|
"issue": "2", |
|
"pages": "249--254", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Jean Carletta. 1996. Assessing agreement on classi- fication tasks: The kappa statistic. Computational Linguistics, 22(2):249-254.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF5": { |
|
"ref_id": "b5", |
|
"title": "Contributing to discourse", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "H", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Herbert", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Edward", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"F" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Clark", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Schaefer", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1989, |
|
"venue": "Cognitive Science", |
|
"volume": "13", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "259--294", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Herbert H. Clark and Edward F. Schaefer. 1989. Con- tributing to discourse. Cognitive Science, 13:259- 294.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF6": { |
|
"ref_id": "b6", |
|
"title": "A statistical filter for resolving pronoun references", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Ido", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Dagan", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Alon", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Itai", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1991, |
|
"venue": "Artificial Intelligence and Computer Vision", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "125--135", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Ido Dagan and Alon Itai. 1991. A statistical filter for resolving pronoun references. In Y.A. Feldman and A. Bruckstein, editors, Artificial Intelligence and Computer Vision, pages 125-135. Elsevier, Amster- dam.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF7": { |
|
"ref_id": "b7", |
|
"title": "What happens when we use an anaphor", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Christina", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Dahl", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hellman", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1995, |
|
"venue": "Presentation at the XVth Scandinavian Conference of Linguistics Oslo", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "t3sten Dahl and Christina Hellman. 1995. What hap- pens when we use an anaphor. In Presentation at the XVth Scandinavian Conference of Linguistics Oslo, Norway.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF8": { |
|
"ref_id": "b8", |
|
"title": "Contributions of verb bias and plausibility to the comprehension of temporarily ambiguous sentences", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Susan", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Garnsey", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Neal", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Pearlmutter", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Elizabeth", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Myers", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Melanie", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Lotocky", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1997, |
|
"venue": "Journal of Memory and Language", |
|
"volume": "37", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "58--93", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Susan Garnsey, Neal Pearlmutter, Elizabeth Myers, and Melanie Lotocky. 1997. Contributions of verb bias and plausibility to the comprehension of tem- porarily ambiguous sentences. Journal of Memory and Language, 37:58-93.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF9": { |
|
"ref_id": "b9", |
|
"title": "Centering: A framework for modeling the local coherence of discourse", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Barbara", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"J" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Grosz", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Aravind", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"K" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Joshi", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Scott", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Weinstein", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1995, |
|
"venue": "Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "21", |
|
"issue": "2", |
|
"pages": "203--225", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Barbara J. Grosz, Aravind K. Joshi, and Scott Wein- stein. 1995. Centering: A framework for modeling the local coherence of discourse. Computational Linguistics, 21 (2):203-225.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF10": { |
|
"ref_id": "b10", |
|
"title": "Cognitive status and the form of referring expressions in discourse", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Jeanette", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"K" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Gundel", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Nancy", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Hedberg", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Ron", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Zacharski", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1993, |
|
"venue": "Language", |
|
"volume": "69", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "274--307", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Jeanette K. Gundel, Nancy Hedberg, and Ron Zacharski. 1993. Cognitive status and the form of referring expressions in discourse. Language, 69:274-307.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF11": { |
|
"ref_id": "b11", |
|
"title": "Arbitrary plural pronominals. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Osvaldo", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Jaeggli", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1986, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "4", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "43--76", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Osvaldo Jaeggli. 1986. Arbitrary plural pronominals. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 4:43-76.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF12": { |
|
"ref_id": "b12", |
|
"title": "Linguistic Data Consortium", |
|
"authors": [], |
|
"year": null, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "LDC. 1993. Switchboard. Linguistic Data Con- sortium. University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, Penn.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF13": { |
|
"ref_id": "b13", |
|
"title": "The representation of multimodal user interface dialogues using discourse pegs", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Susann", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Luperfoy", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1992, |
|
"venue": "Proceedings of the 30 th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "22--31", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Susann LuperFoy. 1992. The representation of mul- timodal user interface dialogues using discourse pegs. In Proceedings of the 30 th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics, Newark, Del., 28 June -2 July 1992, pages 22-31.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF14": { |
|
"ref_id": "b14", |
|
"title": "Discourse segmentation by human and automated means", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Rebecca", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Passonneau", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Diane", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Litman", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1997, |
|
"venue": "Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "23", |
|
"issue": "1", |
|
"pages": "103--139", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Rebecca Passonneau and Diane Litman. 1997. Discourse segmentation by human and automated means. Computational Linguistics, 23(1): 103-139.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF15": { |
|
"ref_id": "b15", |
|
"title": "Expletive noun phrases in subcategorized positions", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Paul", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Postal", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Geoffrey", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Pullum", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1988, |
|
"venue": "Linguistic Inquiry", |
|
"volume": "19", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "635--670", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Paul Postal and Geoffrey Pullum. 1988. Expletive noun phrases in subcategorized positions. Linguis- tic Inquiry, 19:635-670.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF16": { |
|
"ref_id": "b16", |
|
"title": "Never look back: An alternative to centering", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Michael", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Strube", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1998, |
|
"venue": "Proceedings of the 17 th International Conference on Computational Linguistics and 36 th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "1251--1257", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Michael Strube. 1998. Never look back: An alter- native to centering. In Proceedings of the 17 th In- ternational Conference on Computational Linguis- tics and 36 th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics, Montrfal, Qurbec, Canada, 10-14 August 1998, pages 1251-1257.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF17": { |
|
"ref_id": "b17", |
|
"title": "A Computational Theory of Grounding in Natural Language Conversation", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "R", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "David", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Traum", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1994, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "David R. Traum. 1994. A Computational The- ory of Grounding in Natural Language Conversa- tion. Ph:D. thesis, Department of Computer Sci- ence, University of Rochester.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF18": { |
|
"ref_id": "b18", |
|
"title": "Centering, anaphora resolution, and discourse structure", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "A", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Marilyn", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"first": "", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Walker", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1998, |
|
"venue": "Centering Theory in Discourse", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "401--435", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Marilyn A. Walker. 1998. Centering, anaphora res- olution, and discourse structure. In M.A. Walker, A.K. Joshi, and E.E Prince, editors, Centering The- ory in Discourse, pages 401-435. Oxford Univer- sity Press, Oxford, U.K.", |
|
"links": null |
|
}, |
|
"BIBREF19": { |
|
"ref_id": "b19", |
|
"title": "Structure and ostension in the interpretation of discourse deixis", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "Bonnie", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"L" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Webber", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": 1991, |
|
"venue": "Language and Cognitive Processes", |
|
"volume": "6", |
|
"issue": "2", |
|
"pages": "107--135", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Bonnie L. Webber. 1991. Structure and ostension in the interpretation of discourse deixis. Language and Cognitive Processes, 6(2): 107-135.", |
|
"links": null |
|
} |
|
}, |
|
"ref_entries": { |
|
"FIGREF0": { |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"text": "Figure 1below, taken from the Trains-corpus (speakers s and u) illustrates that a missing acknowl-edgment prevents the discourse model from containing discourse entities from the unacknowledged turn.SUi I s: so there-the five boxcars of oranges <sil> + that are at-+ S-List: [5 boxcars of oranges] SUj A/I u: +at <sil> +atComing S-List: [5 boxcars of oranges, the orange warehouse <sil> urn I + have to + S-List: [Coming, orange warehouse] SUk I S: yOU need + you need to get five <sil> five boxcars of oranges there S-List: [Coming, 5 boxcars of oranges] A u: uh SOt I no they're are already waiting for me there (d92a-4.3) Figure 1: Unacknowledged Turns", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure" |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF1": { |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"text": "I-Incompatibility and A-Incompatibility means preferentially associated with abstract objects and A-incompatible means preferentially associated with individual objects 1. Anaphors which are argument positions of the first type are classified as discourse deictic (DDPro; DDDem), those in argument positions of the second type are classified as individual anaphora (IPro; IDem).", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure" |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF2": { |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"text": "Figure 3: Context Ranking", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure" |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF3": { |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"text": "Demonstrative Resolution Algorithm success of the resolution. The function resolvelnd is evaluated first (3) because of the observed preference for individual antecedents for pronouns,.", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure" |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF4": { |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"text": ": resolveDD checked without success, resolveDD returns false (4).", |
|
"num": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure" |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF2": { |
|
"html": null, |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"text": "", |
|
"content": "<table><tr><td>4784</td></tr><tr><td>4705</td></tr><tr><td>0.9835</td></tr><tr><td>0.7890</td></tr><tr><td>0.9217</td></tr><tr><td>: Dialogue Act Units</td></tr></table>", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF4": { |
|
"html": null, |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"text": "Table 32shows the reliability scores for the classification of pronouns in the classes IPro, DDPro, VagPro, and IEProclassification of demonstratives in the classes IDem, DDDem, ~ and VagDem. The e-values are around .8, indicating that annotators were able to classify the pronouns reliably.", |
|
"content": "<table><tr><td/><td colspan=\"3\">SW2403 SW3117 SW3241</td><td/></tr><tr><td>IPro</td><td>120</td><td>148</td><td>5</td><td>273</td></tr><tr><td>DDPro</td><td>33</td><td>5</td><td>9</td><td>47</td></tr><tr><td>VagPro</td><td>31</td><td>20</td><td>26</td><td>77</td></tr><tr><td>IEPro</td><td>24</td><td>20</td><td>86</td><td>130</td></tr><tr><td>N</td><td>104</td><td>97</td><td>63</td><td>264</td></tr><tr><td>Z</td><td>83</td><td>90</td><td>58</td><td>231</td></tr><tr><td>PA</td><td>0.7980</td><td>0.9278</td><td>0.9206</td><td>0.8750</td></tr><tr><td>PE</td><td>0.3935</td><td>0.6039</td><td>0.5151</td><td>0.3571</td></tr><tr><td/><td>0.6670</td><td>0.8170</td><td>0.8363</td><td>0.8055</td></tr></table>", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF5": { |
|
"html": null, |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"text": "", |
|
"content": "<table><tr><td/><td colspan=\"3\">: Classification of Pronouns</td><td/></tr><tr><td/><td colspan=\"3\">SW2403 SW3117 SW3241</td><td>E</td></tr><tr><td>IDem</td><td>9</td><td>19</td><td>2</td><td>30</td></tr><tr><td>DDDem</td><td>45</td><td>34</td><td>28</td><td>107</td></tr><tr><td>VagDem</td><td>5</td><td>3</td><td>6</td><td>14</td></tr><tr><td>N</td><td>30</td><td>28</td><td>18</td><td>76</td></tr><tr><td>Z</td><td>27</td><td>26</td><td>16</td><td>69</td></tr><tr><td>PA</td><td>0.9000</td><td>0.9286</td><td>0.8888</td><td>0.9078</td></tr><tr><td>PE</td><td>0.5919</td><td>0.4866</td><td>0.6358</td><td>0.5430</td></tr><tr><td/><td>0.7550</td><td>0.8609</td><td>0.6949</td><td>0.7985</td></tr></table>", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF6": { |
|
"html": null, |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"text": "Classification of Demonstratives", |
|
"content": "<table/>", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF8": { |
|
"html": null, |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"text": "Agreement about Antecedents of Discourse Deictic Anaphora against Key", |
|
"content": "<table/>", |
|
"num": null |
|
}, |
|
"TABREF10": { |
|
"html": null, |
|
"type_str": "table", |
|
"text": "Results of the Discourse Deictic Anaphora Algorithm", |
|
"content": "<table/>", |
|
"num": null |
|
} |
|
} |
|
} |
|
} |