Benjamin Aw
Add updated pkl file v3
6fa4bc9
{
"paper_id": "T87-1020",
"header": {
"generated_with": "S2ORC 1.0.0",
"date_generated": "2023-01-19T07:43:32.895097Z"
},
"title": "Towards a Semantic Theory of Discourse",
"authors": [
{
"first": "C",
"middle": [
"Raymond"
],
"last": "Perrault",
"suffix": "",
"affiliation": {},
"email": ""
}
],
"year": "",
"venue": null,
"identifiers": {},
"abstract": "",
"pdf_parse": {
"paper_id": "T87-1020",
"_pdf_hash": "",
"abstract": [],
"body_text": [
{
"text": "I don't feel comfortable trying to building reliable, well-understood NLP systems without providing a semantics for their \"mental state,\" including the data structures they encode. One step in that direction is a semantics of sentences, for example that of Montague. However, to handle extended discourses, the methods of model-theoretic semantics need to be extended in (at least) three directions. First, anaphora and deixis require that the interpretation (of phrases, sentences, and entire discourses) should be made sensitive to context, both linguistic and physical. Second, non-declarative sentences must be treated uniformly with declarative ones. Finally, it should be possible to make room in the semantics for interpretation constraints based on the subject-matter of the discourse and on communication itself. I'm thinking particularly of the kind of inferences typically captured computationally by the use of scripts, plans, prototypes, etc.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Typically these constraints on interpretations have been kept outside the realm of semantics, and might even be taken .to be the distinguishing characteristics of a separate pragrnatics component. I'd like to suggest that we already have available many of the necessary elements for a context-sensitive theory of discourse, although substantial work still needs to be done to bring the pieces together and to build implementations faithful to the semantics.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Several proposals have now been made to account for possible relations between anaphora and antecedents within and across sentences, including treatments of the interaction between quantifiers and anaphors [W, K, H, B] . Kamp and Heim both introduce an intermediate lev.,el of representation of sentences and give a semantics to that level while Barwise's syntax-directed interpretation relation also takes as arguments input and output contexts which are partial assignments of values to variables. However, none of these treatments takes into consideration the domain constraints, perhaps better described as preferences, or those discussed by Grosz et al. [G] under the name ofcentering.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 206,
"end": 218,
"text": "[W, K, H, B]",
"ref_id": null
},
{
"start": 659,
"end": 662,
"text": "[G]",
"ref_id": null
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "I used to think of the interpretation of non-declarative sentences as being outside the domain of semantics; it wasn't clear how semantics was compatible with the attribution of illocutionary force (or speech act type) to utterances. But a uniform semantics for different sentence types is possible if one takes the interpretation of an utterance (of any number of sentences) to be a relation, determined by mood, intonation, and propositional contet~t, between the joint mental state of the participants before and after the utterance. The speech acts (illocutionary and perlocutionary) applicable to the utterance are then determinable as a function of the initial mental state of the speaker (in the case ofillocutionary acts, such as assert and warn) or of both initial and final mental states ofspeaker and hearer (in the case of perlocutionary acts, such as conoince and scare). The beginning of such an analysis can be found in [PJ. There are other good reasons for this move. It treats utterances as first-class actions, making it possible to use them in complex actions including non-linguistic acts. It also makes it easier to show the relation between illocutionary acts and the related intended periocutionary effects. It also makes it possible to show what are the consequences of utterances which, intentionally or not, violate the normal conventions, as is the case with ironical, indirect and insincere utterances. The key feature of the analysis is its dependence on default rules, formulated within Reiter's non-monotonic default logic [R] . to express the consequences of utterances, making clear that the conveyance of propositional attitudes constituting a speech act is based on the use of utterances with certain features in mental states appropriate to the attitudes being conveyed, but that, in general, the speaker need not be in the requisite mental state.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 1554,
"end": 1557,
"text": "[R]",
"ref_id": null
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Several other discourse constraints have been studied in the framework of various non-monotonic logics (e.g., presupposition [M] , anaphora resolu.tion [D] , conversational implicature [d] .) So have questions with obvious relation to.discourse such as plan .recognition [KA] and temporal reasoning IS, L]... Script-based reasoning should allow the defeasible inference of the existence'of various entities, including events, from the statement of the existence of related entities.",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 125,
"end": 128,
"text": "[M]",
"ref_id": null
},
{
"start": 152,
"end": 155,
"text": "[D]",
"ref_id": null
},
{
"start": 185,
"end": 188,
"text": "[d]",
"ref_id": null
},
{
"start": 271,
"end": 275,
"text": "[KA]",
"ref_id": null
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Although non-monotonic reasoning seems to hold the key to a wide range ofdiscourse phenomena, the developments above appeal to a range of different systems: in fact, no two of the papers mentioned above use exactly the same system. One promising area of unification of the various systems is through their use of preferred models. It may be useful to start with a familiar case. In Montague grammar (based on intensional logic, a monotonic system), it is possible to specify constraints on lexical items (e.g. the fact that seek is equivalent to try to find, or that the subject of seek, is extensional, or human) in a set of meaning postulates. These postulates are used to restrict the class of models considered: a sentence s is valid iffit is true in all models satisfying the meaning postulates. Similarly, various non-monotonic theories are given semantics by restricting the models in which they are interpreted. McCarthy's circumscription, for example, makes use of models in which certain predicates are restricted to their smallest extensions; Shoham's logic of chronological ignorance depends on what he calls chronologically maximally ignorant models, and Kautz's logic ofplans minimises over several dimensions, including, e.g., the number of steps in a plan.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "The whole area of non-monotonic reasoning is in a state of great flux, in part because of the diversity of systems and the technical difficulty of arguments within and between the various systems [HM] . Nevertheless, the simple fact that no other approach comes close to dealing with so many of the relevant problems suggests to me that three questions should be investigated on the way to a semantic theory of discourse:",
"cite_spans": [
{
"start": 196,
"end": 200,
"text": "[HM]",
"ref_id": null
}
],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "\u2022 whether other \"pragmatic\" problems can be couched in the same terms (e.g., noun-noun modification, metonymy, word-sense selection),",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "\u2022 whether there is a general enough notion of preference to cover all these cases,",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "\u2022 whether a positive answer to these questions can be translated into processing algorithms.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
},
{
"text": "Maybe we'll know the answers at the next meeting.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "",
"sec_num": null
}
],
"back_matter": [
{
"text": "This paper was made possible by a gift from the Systems Developement Foundation.",
"cite_spans": [],
"ref_spans": [],
"eq_spans": [],
"section": "Acknowledgement",
"sec_num": null
}
],
"bib_entries": {
"BIBREF0": {
"ref_id": "b0",
"title": "Noun phrases, generalized quantifiers and anaphora",
"authors": [
{
"first": "K",
"middle": [
"J"
],
"last": "Barwise",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1986,
"venue": "CSLI report",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "86--52",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Barwise, K.J., Noun phrases, generalized quantifiers and anaphora, CSLI report 86-52, 1986.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF1": {
"ref_id": "b1",
"title": "Default reasoning in anaphora resolution",
"authors": [
{
"first": "B",
"middle": [],
"last": "Dunin-Keplicz",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1984,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Dunin-Keplicz, B., Default reasoning in anaphora resolution, ECAI-84, 1984.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF2": {
"ref_id": "b2",
"title": "Providing a unified account of definite noun phrases in discourse",
"authors": [
{
"first": "B",
"middle": [
"J"
],
"last": "Grosz",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "A",
"middle": [
"K"
],
"last": "Joshi",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "S",
"middle": [],
"last": "Weinstein",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1983,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Grosz, B.J., Joshi, A.K., Weinstein, S., Providing a unified account of definite noun phrases in discourse, ACL-21, 1983.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF3": {
"ref_id": "b3",
"title": "Default reasoning, nonmonotonic logics, and the frame problem",
"authors": [
{
"first": "S",
"middle": [],
"last": "Hanks",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "D",
"middle": [],
"last": "Mcdermott",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1986,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Hanks, S., McDermott, D., Default reasoning, nonmonotonic logics, and the frame problem, AAAI-86, 1986.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF4": {
"ref_id": "b4",
"title": "Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases, PhD Dissertation",
"authors": [
{
"first": "I",
"middle": [],
"last": "Heim",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1982,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Heim, I. Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases, PhD Dissertation, Univ. of Massachusetts, Amhest, 1982.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF5": {
"ref_id": "b5",
"title": "Some aspects of default reasoning in interactive discourse, Univ. of Penn",
"authors": [
{
"first": "A",
"middle": [
"K"
],
"last": "Joshi",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "B",
"middle": [
"L"
],
"last": "Webber",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "R",
"middle": [
"M"
],
"last": "Weischedel",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1986,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Joshi, A.K., Webber, B.L., Weischedel, R.M., Some aspects of default reasoning in interactive discourse, Univ. of Penn. Tech Note MS-CIS-86-27, 1986.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF6": {
"ref_id": "b6",
"title": "A theory of truth and semantic representation",
"authors": [
{
"first": "H",
"middle": [],
"last": "Kamp",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1981,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Kamp, H. A theory of truth and semantic representation, in J. Groenendijk et al (eds.) Formal Methods in the Study of Language, Amsterdam, Math. Center, 1981.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF7": {
"ref_id": "b7",
"title": "Generalized plan recognition",
"authors": [
{
"first": "H",
"middle": [
"K"
],
"last": "Kautz",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "J",
"middle": [
"F"
],
"last": "Allen",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1986,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Kautz, H.K., Allen, J.F., Generalized plan recognition, AAAI-86, 1986.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF8": {
"ref_id": "b8",
"title": "Pointwise circumscription, AAAI-86",
"authors": [
{
"first": "V",
"middle": [],
"last": "Lifschitz",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1986,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Lifschitz, V., Pointwise circumscription, AAAI-86, 1986.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF9": {
"ref_id": "b9",
"title": "The representation ofdefaults using defaults, UBC Tech",
"authors": [
{
"first": "R",
"middle": [],
"last": "Mercer",
"suffix": ""
},
{
"first": "R",
"middle": [],
"last": "Reiter",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1982,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Mercer, R. and Reiter, R., The representation ofdefaults using defaults, UBC Tech. Report, 1982.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF10": {
"ref_id": "b10",
"title": "An application ofdefault logic to speech act theory",
"authors": [
{
"first": "C",
"middle": [
"R"
],
"last": "Perrault",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": null,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Perrault, C.R., An application ofdefault logic to speech act theory, in preparation.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF11": {
"ref_id": "b11",
"title": "A logic for default reasoning",
"authors": [
{
"first": "R",
"middle": [],
"last": "Jr] Reiter",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1980,
"venue": "Art. Int",
"volume": "13",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "JR] Reiter, R. A logic for default reasoning, Art. Int., 13, 1980.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF12": {
"ref_id": "b12",
"title": "Chronological ignorance, AAAI-86",
"authors": [
{
"first": "Y",
"middle": [],
"last": "Shoham",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1986,
"venue": "",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Shoham, Y., Chronological ignorance, AAAI-86, 1986.",
"links": null
},
"BIBREF13": {
"ref_id": "b13",
"title": "So what can we talk about now?",
"authors": [
{
"first": "B",
"middle": [
"L"
],
"last": "Webber",
"suffix": ""
}
],
"year": 1983,
"venue": "Computational Models of Discourse",
"volume": "",
"issue": "",
"pages": "",
"other_ids": {},
"num": null,
"urls": [],
"raw_text": "Webber, B.L., So what can we talk about now?, in Brady and Berwick (eds.), Computational Models of Discourse, MIT Press, 1983.",
"links": null
}
},
"ref_entries": {}
}
}