File size: 46,272 Bytes
dae990d
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
1162
1163
1164
1165
1166
1167
1168
1169
1170
1171
1172
1173
1174
1175
1176
1177
1178
1179
1180
1181
1182
1183
1184
1185
1186
1187
1188
1189
1190
1191
1192
1193
1194
1195
1196
1197
1198
1199
1200
1201
1202
1203
1204
1205
1206
1207
1208
1209
1210
1211
1212
1213
1214
1215
1216
1217
1218
1219
1220
1221
1222
1223
1224
1225
1226
1227
1228
1229
1230
1231
1232
1233
1234
1235
1236
1237
1238
1239
1240
1241
1242
1243
1244
1245
1246
1247
1248
1249
1250
1251
1252
1253
1254
1255
1256
1257
1258
1259
1260
1261
1262
1263
1264
1265
1266
1267
1268
1269
1270
1271
1272
1273
1274
1275
1276
1277
1278
1279
1280
1281
1282
1283
1284
1285
1286
1287
1288
1289
1290
1291
1292
1293
1294
1295
1296
1297
1298
1299
1300
1301
1302
1303
1304
1305
1306
1307
1308
1309
1310
1311
1312
1313
1314
1315
1316
1317
1318
1319
1320
1321
1322
1323
1324
1325
1326
1327
1328
1329
1330
1331
1332
1333
1334
1335
1336
1337
1338
1339
1340
1341
1342
1343
1344
1345
1346
1347
1348
1349
1350
1351
1352
1353
1354
1355
1356
1357
1358
1359
1360
1361
1362
1363
1364
1365
1366
1367
1368
1369
1370
1371
1372
1373
1374
1375
1376
1377
1378
1379
1380
1381
1382
1383
1384
1385
1386
1387
1388
1389
1390
1391
1392
1393
1394
1395
1396
1397
1398
1399
1400
1401
1402
1403
1404
1405
1406
1407
1408
1409
1410
1411
1412
1413
1414
1415
1416
1417
1418
1419
1420
1421
1422
1423
1424
1425
1426
1427
1428
1429
1430
1431
1432
1433
1434
1435
1436
1437
1438
1439
1440
1441
1442
1443
1444
1445
1446
1447
1448
1449
1450
1451
1452
1453
1454
1455
1456
1457
1458
1459
1460
1461
1462
1463
1464
1465
1466
1467
1468
1469
1470
1471
1472
1473
1474
1475
1476
1477
1478
1479
1480
1481
1482
1483
1484
1485
1486
1487
1488
1489
1490
1491
1492
1493
1494
1495
1496
1497
1498
1499
1500
1501
1502
1503
1504
1505
1506
1507
1508
1509
1510
1511
1512
1513
1514
1515
1516
1517
1518
1519
1520
1521
1522
1523
1524
1525
1526
1527
1528
1529
1530
1531
1532
1533
1534
1535
1536
1537
1538
1539
1540
1541
1542
1543
1544
1545
1546
1547
1548
1549
1550
1551
1552
1553
1554
1555
1556
1557
1558
1559
1560
1561
1562
1563
1564
1565
1566
1567
1568
1569
1570
1571
1572
1573
1574
1575
1576
1577
1578
1579
1580
1581
1582
1583
1584
1585
1586
1587
1588
1589
1590
1591
1592
1593
1594
1595
1596
1597
1598
1599
1600
1601
1602
1603
1604
1605
1606
1607
1608
1609
1610
1611
1612
1613
1614
1615
1616
1617
1618
1619
1620
1621
1622
1623
1624
1625
1626
1627
1628
1629
1630
1631
1632
1633
1634
1635
1636
1637
1638
1639
1640
1641
1642
1643
1644
1645
1646
1647
1648
1649
1650
1651
1652
1653
1654
1655
1656
1657
1658
1659
1660
1661
1662
1663
1664
1665
1666
1667
1668
1669
1670
1671
1672
1673
1674
1675
1676
1677
1678
1679
1680
1681
1682
1683
1684
1685
1686
1687
1688
1689
1690
1691
1692
1693
1694
1695
1696
1697
1698
1699
1700
1701
1702
1703
1704
1705
1706
1707
1708
1709
1710
1711
1712
1713
1714
1715
1716
1717
1718
1719
1720
1721
1722
1723
1724
1725
1726
1727
1728
1729
1730
1731
1732
1733
1734
1735
1736
1737
1738
1739
1740
1741
1742
1743
1744
1745
1746
1747
1748
1749
1750
1751
1752
1753
1754
1755
1756
1757
1758
1759
1760
1761
1762
1763
1764
1765
1766
1767
1768
1769
1770
1771
1772
1773
1774
1775
1776
1777
1778
1779
1780
1781
1782
1783
1784
1785
1786
1787
1788
1789
1790
1791
1792
1793
1794
1795
1796
1797
1798
1799
1800
1801
1802
1803
1804
1805
1806
1807
1808
1809
1810
1811
1812
1813
1814
1815
1816
1817
1818
1819
1820
1821
1822
1823
1824
1825
1826
1827
1828
1829
1830
1831
1832
1833
1834
1835
1836
1837
1838
1839
1840
1841
1842
1843
1844
1845
1846
1847
1848
1849
1850
1851
1852
1853
1854
1855
1856
1857
1858
1859
1860
1861
1862
1863
1864
1865
1866
1867
1868
1869
1870
1871
1872
1873
1874
1875
1876
1877
1878
1879
1880
1881
1882
1883
1884
1885
1886
1887
1888
1889
1890
1891
1892
1893
1894
1895
1896
1897
1898
1899
1900
1901
1902
1903
1904
1905
1906
1907
1908
1909
1910
1911
1912
1913
1914
1915
1916
1917
1918
1919
1920
1921
1922
1923
1924
1925
1926
1927
1928
1929
1930
1931
1932
1933
1934
1935
1936
1937
1938
1939
1940
1941
1942
1943
1944
1945
1946
1947
1948
1949
1950
1951
1952
1953
1954
1955
1956
1957
1958
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963
1964
1965
1966
1967
1968
1969
1970
1971
1972
1973
1974
1975
1976
1977
1978
1979
1980
1981
1982
1983
1984
1985
1986
1987
1988
1989
1990
1991
1992
1993
1994
1995
1996
1997
1998
1999
2000
2001
2002
2003
2004
2005
2006
2007
2008
2009
2010
2011
2012
2013
2014
2015
2016
2017
2018
2019
2020
2021
2022
2023
2024
2025
2026
2027
2028
2029
Okay.

So my name is Steve Fleming, and I'm going to

be giving you a lecture on consciousness today.

I am.

So what's the focus of this lecture is is the

problem of perceptual awareness.

So imagine your standing on whatever bridge this would be

in London.

Mostly bridges, maybe.

And you're looking at the sunset.

Then you will also be most likely to be aware

of that sunset and be able to communicate its properties

to other people, to your friends and so on.

But at the same time, there's a lot of other

perceptual inputs that you may well be unaware of, such

as the feeling of the clothes on your skin or

changes in your posture.

And a cool question in consciousness science is what are

the computations in the brain that differentiate between conscious and

unconscious information and what are the mechanisms, what the neural

mechanisms that supports that difference.

Now, when you hear the word consciousness, people often start

thinking about mysterious phenomena.

So in the media you might hear about panpsychism or

plants, consciousness and so on.

So we're not going to be encroaching on this territory

today.

So there are some somewhat out there consciousness that are

doing the rounds and we can't rule them out 100%.

But the approach I'm going to tell you about today

is taking an approach very much squarely within cognitive psychology

and neuroscience.

And the questions that we can tackle with experiments in

the lab are these ones.

So what differentiates Conscious from unconscious processing as a neural

level?

What is it in the brain that makes a difference

for conscious processing?

What's the difference that makes the difference?

So in today's lecture, there's quite a lot to get

through.

There's a bit of material towards the end of the

lecture, which is some unpublished work from my lab that

is optional.

It won't be examined, for instance, is not published, but

if we get there, then I can talk about it,

but I might skip over that if we are short

of time.

So we're going to cover these topics.

Conscious the difference between conscious level and conscious concepts, and

talk briefly about some methods for manipulation in consciousness in

the lab.

Talk briefly about what's been found, found out about the

neural collective consciousness, and then I'll talk about some theoretical

issues, such as the importance of controlling for performance.

And then at the end, we'll look at some ethical

issues that arise.

Well, it's now become possible to detect the presence or

absence of consciousness in non responsive individuals.

So what do we mean by the difference between consent

and level of consciousness?

So the idea here is that we differentiate in the

level of consciousness from, say, sleep to wake you go

you become unconscious when you are in a dreamless sleep,

you then maybe become conscious of your dreams, and then

when you wake up in the morning, you're fully conscious

of the outside world.

So that's different, a difference in the level of consciousness.

But the idea is that even when conscious level is

constant, so even when you are awake and engaged in

your surroundings, then the content of your consciousness might fluctuate

over time.

So you might be conscious of my voice right now,

but in a few minutes, if you zone out for

a few seconds, think about something else.

You might not be conscious of my voice in in,

in, in that in that moment of time.

So the question that we're going to focus on in

the main question we have to focus on today is

what contributes to conscious experience over and above simple information

processing.

The information is getting processed to some level.

We know that from experiments, so I'll talk about next.

But sometimes it's conscious and sometimes it's not.

What makes what underpins that difference.

So a lot of the work that's been done to

study consciousness in the lab has been a variant on

a paradigm called visual masking, which some of you may

have heard about, say masking is quite simple.

The idea is that you present a stimulus on a

screen and then a very short time later you present

a mask.

And the the time interval between the stimulus and the

mask is known as the entire stimulus interval is I.

And sometimes you'll see that written in papers.

Is the stimulus onset a synchrony or the way those

two terms are interchangeable?

And that's in say, Sorry, I should have told you

to be ready for this.

So if you have a look at the screen now,

I'm going to flash up an example of a mask.

So some hashtags followed by the stimulus, followed by the

happens again.

And you should be able to see this one.

Let's just back up.

So we're ready.

Here we go.

Everyone see what the word was.

Okay.

So that was a relatively long as.

So the word is visible.

This is now a shorter AISI.

And it isn't even sure to ISI.

He put your hand up if you saw the.

Okay.

So about 50%.

So that's that's.

So, I mean, PowerPoint is not the best technology for

presenting these kind of stimuli, but as easy as the

mask and the stimulus interval decreases, it becomes harder and

harder to see.

The word that last one was orange for those of

you who saw it.

So the masking effectiveness has been studied in a number

of studies.

It depends on the timing, as we've seen.

It also depends on the stimulus intensity.

So if I keep the icy effects and drop the

contrast of the how black or grey that stabilises, then

I can increase the masking efficacy and also stimulus content.

So interestingly, things like your own name or emotion always

will jump out even the same level of masking.

And there are also individual differences, as we saw.

So some people saw it, some people didn't.

This is obviously not a control.

It's like a business experiment.

But when we do controls like this on this, we

see individual differences in masking threshold.

Now, this would be less interesting if this just meant

that you didn't see the work.

It wasn't even processed on your retina, for instance.

That would be less interesting because that just means the

stimulus hasn't got into the system.

But we know from a number of studies in cognitive

psychology that mass stimuli can affect behaviour even when people

say they didn't see it.

So often this is done using what's known as an

indirect test of and the processing of the words.

So you might go through an initial phase of an

experiment where you get flash words or different stimuli that

were masked.

And on some trials of that experiment, you might say,

I didn't see it.

I don't know what the word was.

But then in a second, indirect test, for instance, this

is an example from ten up in the eighties.

If you then ask people to say whether somebody is

a word or a non word, you'll be faster.

If the word is semantically related to the last word

that you claimed not to see.

So in this case, banana is semantically related to orange

and you're faster to say that you banana is a

word.

So that indicates some depth of processing.

It's not just that it's failed to get into the

system on the retina.

It's got into the system.

But people still claim that on the Web.

Now, more recently, people have used brain imaging to show

that it's at least into the visual system.

And even they're processed into, say, areas dealing with language.

So this is an experiment from Garrett Research Group in

Queen Square.

And what they did here was use masking to make

the orientation of these lines invisible.

And they used a slightly more sophisticated masking procedure so

they could, rather than just flush it once, they could

flush it continuously.

And people would still claim not to see the orientation

of the grating.

Right.

So that what they're actually being flashed is a left

tilted or a right tilted grating.

But they just see a mask, applied mask.

And what you see on the right, that it's a

machine learning classifier that's trained to try and decode the

true orientation of the invisible grating from activation of different

brain areas.

And as you can see, they can decode above channels

and the visual cortex.

So that suggests that the grating is being processed in

early visual cortex, even though the subjects themselves say they

didn't see it.

So that's some evidence, both behavioural and hopeful.

The processing of stimuli without awareness.

Then what happens when you become aware of it?

This is the other side of the coin.

And so when you do this, you can show that

when you see a masked word.

Then you get elevated activation in a widespread network in

the frontal cortex, whereas when the word is invisible, then

the activation is much more restricted to early visual areas.

I can't find a pointer, but not read is maybe

I can come up.

Yeah, I think.

Yes.

Good.

So this.

This.

This red blob on the right hand side here is

the activation you would get in individual cortex X to

straight cortex when word is invisible compared to baselines, suggesting,

again, like any experiment, some processing of my stimuli in

early visual areas.

But when you become aware of it, when you see

it, you see it and you get much more widespread

activation in your friends across the network.

These are experiments.

These are both experiments from Standard Hands Group reviewed in

this paper newsroom.

Again, you get a similar pattern when it's in the

auditorium with a mask.

Or interestingly, in white noise.

Sometimes you say you see it, you heard it, sometimes

you didn't.

When you didn't.

When you say you didn't hear, hear it, you get

some activation in auditory cortex suggesting some data processing.

But when you say you heard it and you get

much more widespread activation in front of prosecutors.

We'll come back to what this means in a second.

Just for completeness, another popular technique for manipulating an awareness

of the stimulus is binocular rivalry.

So often this is done using red green goggles.

So you present an overlapping stimulus.

So the house is in red here, the face is

in green.

If you put red green goggles on, the images compete

for dominance between the two eyes.

Sometimes you see the faces, sometimes you see the house.

But the stimulus that's on the screen is identical in

both cases.

And so this is useful because then you can create

this kind of phenomenon where there's an unchanging stimulus, but

your perception is changing.

And when the stimulus is unconscious, we can also track

it.

We can then track its influence on information processing.

So just to give you one example of work in

this.

So here is a study from Dell PCS Group.

What they did here was used by knock the rivalry

to mask the movement of some moving dots.

So this is the this is the stimulus that people

actually see in the other eye.

What they don't see is some coherently moving dots.

And then after this initial period of binocular rivalry, they

have to make a decision about some consciously moving dots.

And what they find is that if the unconscious information

is helpful and people will be better at that decision

when it's coherent in red than when it's just random

and in green.

But interestingly, this so this unconscious information boost your performance.

So again, it shows the process, but it doesn't change

people's confidence in that decision.

So to them, subjectively, subjectively, it feels as though it's

just the same in both the helpful and the unhelpful

cases.

But in the helpful cases, even though the information is

unconscious, it's actually making your decision better.

So we can then ask and we've already seen some

of this information already.

What are the what are the new correlates of consciousness?

So we know that we can input information into the

system that is sometimes unconscious.

So then we want to know what's the difference between

when you're conscious of a stimulus and when you're not.

And so the neural correlates of consciousness have been defined

in the early 2000s as the minimal set of neural

events that are sufficient for a specific conscious experience.

So the idea here is to keep the stimulus inputs

similar, but contrast conditions between when you say you were

white or something and when you were unaware of something.

Okay, so we've already seen this slide.

So this is the idea.

When you're aware of something, there is a global ignition

through the brain, through the frontal and the price of

cortex.

And when you're not aware of that stimulus, you don't

get that global ignition.

So just to give you an detailed example of this,

this is actually from a study using EEG and combined

with Meg.

And so here they were able to look at the

fine grained temporal dynamics of what happens, what the fate

of a stimulus when you show it on the screen,

either when someone says they saw it or when they

didn't see it.

Yeah.

Yeah.

See, that's what you.

Right.

Sorry.

That's actually prefrontal cortex.

But you should.

There is also activation in the parts of what occurs

in the prefrontal cortex and the Bronco area where they

are.

That's right.

That's right.

Yeah.

And so, again, they used this masking procedure with a

variable delay, stimulus onset synchrony.

And what they could then do is plot these activity

time courses as a function of this asset way.

Right.

So people gradually became more and more aware of the

stimulus as the way increased.

And what they found was that in early in early

visual cortex, see this this box here, there was a

pretty linear increase with SLA.

So it's like the stimulus is getting a bit stronger,

a bit stronger, a bit stronger in the early visual

areas.

But when you look at the prefrontal cortex signature later

in the trial, it's more all or nothing.

It's almost as if like on some trials, the whole

system is nice and you're conscious of it.

On other trials, it doesn't.

So this is this idea of a bifurcation response.

So it's like a nonlinear system where occasionally the stimulus

will trigger this ignition and make it into violence, and

other times it won't.

So there's been various models proposed with what might be

going on here.

So one of the most popular ones from the bars

and stand the hands grip.

Has been the global workspace theory of consciousness and the

idea that consciousness occurs once information is may be sequestered

in perceptual areas, gains access to a global neuronal workspace.

And that's proposed to be supported by these fronts of

prior to networks.

And so that would explain why you get ignition, because

when the information is weak or subliminal, it just kind

of reverberates around the visual cortex.

Then as it crosses the threshold for admission into consciousness,

you get recruitment of these fronts across all regions as

well.

An alternative view is the recurrent processing VAT that was

put forward by Ptolemy in the 2000.

Is that.

What happens is that when you get some visual input.

If it's very weak, then you'll just get feed, food

processing and you won't get any conscious person.

But if it's a bit stronger and long lasting, then

you'll get both people and feedback activation along the cortex.

And that supports consciousness.

And what Lamaze this additional ignition into the parts network

is secondary.

It's not causal or conscious experience, but it might be

involved in things like reporting that you've seen something.

So this is quite a deep divide between what are

called local theories of consciousness, which propose the activation in

recurrent loops within the perceptual system are sufficient for consciousness,

experience and global theories which propose you need to get

the information out into a global workspace for consciousness to

arise.

How.

And so so this this activation here would be just

for reporting your experience for assistance, but not for actually

being conscious of that experience.

Then you might be, for instance, you might be conscious

of something and then immediately forget it and be unable

to report it.

And the recovery process.

If you say that your your conscious is in the

moment that is supported by recurrent processing, even though you're

unable to report on it.

Now, personally, I find this new quite difficult to get

my head around because it would suggest that there could

be cases where the subject themselves says, I definitely wasn't

conscious of this thing.

But the neuroscience, as we say now, and I can

see your reverberating loops in your visual cortex, you must

have been conscious of it.

So I think this actually goes against the folk psychological

notion of consciousness is something we're able to communicate to

others.

But I think it's still worth taking seriously.

Okay.

So the final theory I just want to cover is

higher order theory.

This is got similarities with the global workspace theory.

And the idea is that there are first order representations

in perceptual systems, and these first order representations themselves are

not sufficient for conscious experience.

They might drive behaviour, they might allow you to respond

above chance on a task, but they're not sufficient for

conscious experience.

And instead the idea is that consciousness of that content

needs to have some higher order representation that allows the

system to become aware of that first order state.

So this entails that the first order representation in the

perceptual system should be monitored or matter represented by the

higher order representation.

And so that's another prominent view.

And again, with, you know, ongoing debate about which which

view is correct.

And new experiments are coming out all the time to

try and distinguish between them.

And one important issue that we need to do here

affects all these different theories is the problem of performance

compounds.

So when we look at the neural coral, it's a

conscious one.

When we look at the these emission signatures, are we

really just isolating consciousness or are we isolating the neural

correlates of the improved performance or information processing that often

accompanies consciousness?

Because we know that when we're aware, some people are

often able to use that for various functions like Oops.

Like language, working memory, communicating it and so on.

And the reason that is really important to control for

performance is also got its roots in philosophy and in

the theory of consciousness.

So the idea is that consciousness or sentience is not

the same as being sensitive to something.

I say we can think of plenty of systems that

are sensitive to the outside world without being conscious.

Your camera appliance, maybe a thermometer, those all those are

all sensitive to the outside world, but we don't usually

think of them as being conscious of what they are

sensitive to.

And because under some theories like higher order theory, these

first order representations are held to drive tough performance as

well as contribute to consciousness.

The problem is that if we have some experiment that

boosts consciousness in some way, like changing the soul in

a masking experiment, if we change both consciousness and performance

in tandem, then we don't know whether the neural or

behavioural change we see is due to the changes in

performance or the changes in consciousness.

And as I said, this is particularly crucial for testing

the predictions of higher order theories, because if performance is

not controlled, then we might unfairly stack the deck in

favour of these first order theories that might see correlates

of consciousness in only, only perceptual areas.

And if you're interested, this has been really nicely unpacked

in a book.

It's very accessible by heart for love.

So one reason to believe that we can do this

and control for performance and still study consciousness is the

phenomenon of Blind Side that was discovered by Larry Weiss

Krantz, who was a eminent psychologist at Oxford.

And what he did was study patients with damage to

the early visual cortex.

And so these patients would often have time is just

to one hemisphere caused by an injury.

And that led to their clinical visual field tests looking

something like this.

They'd be perfectly well aware of things on one side

of space, but they be essentially blind in the other

side of space.

So when they came into the doctors, when they went

to the apologists, they would be classed as having a

brain lesion causing blindness in one half of space.

But what's really interesting here is that when you study

them in more depth, patients with Blind Eye are actually

able to guess while above chance.

What is being presented in that Blind Army field.

Now, I won't show this just for the sake of

time.

If you're interested, you could watch a YouTube video of

a black patient doing exactly this.

The light lights are flashed in the blind field, and

when he's forced to guess where they were, he's often

close to 100% accurate, even though he himself will say,

I didn't see anything.

Right.

So that's a case of performance being high, but always

being zero.

And in experiments you can then adjust the stimuli in

both the normal and the blind hemi field.

So that performance is matched between the two hemi fields.

But now he's only aware of the stimuli in the

normal hemi field, not aware of the blind happy field

that creates an really nice, well-controlled case where performance is

matched in the two hemi fields.

There's no compounded performance now you're just he's able to

process the information just as well in both cases.

And yet awareness is only present for the stimulation one

field and not the other.

And when we then look at brain activation in relation

to this difference, you still see the controlling performance elevated

activation in the front supports.

In that way when you're presenting stimuli in the normal

impairs the blind.

HAVERFIELD.

It's also possible to do these kind of experiments in

otherwise healthy observers.

So this was a study of blind side in normal

subjects, in healthy subjects without a brain lesion.

And this was done using a masking procedure.

So participants were first asked to decide whether a diamond

or a square was presented on the screen.

And this was difficult because it was masked.

It was flashed very briefly.

And they then had to indicate whether they saw the

target or whether they simply guessed the answer.

And what was found in this experiment was that it

was possible to find two conditions.

Across the whole range of ways where performance was modest.

So that's the the red line here.

Performance at these two areas is matched.

But this is the way people say they saw it

less often than this as a way.

So you can see that down here performance is nicely

matched conditions.

Information processing is just as good.

But people are less aware of the stimulus that this

has away in this X-ray.

And when that contrast is then done between these two

ways within the fMRI scanner, you get localised activation in

the lateral prefrontal cortex in relation to increase in conscious

awareness.

And just a final example of this.

This is from, again, a study of patients with brain

lesions, but now with lesions to the prefrontal cortex.

So patients with prefrontal damage were asked to provide a

false choice of which of to stimuli were presented on

the screen and to rate the visibility of their stimuli.

So how aware they were.

And what's interesting is that compared to controls.

The subjective visibility of those stimuli was reduced in the

patients.

And that's even the case when performance is match between

the controls and on the patients.

Right.

So this is now plotting the the the difference in

visibility for trials on which the patients got correct patients

and controls got correct.

On the upper lines here on trials in which they

got incorrect here.

So even when you split out the trials, according to

ones that there were right and wrong, you still see

that subjective visibility is lower in the patients in grey

compared to the controls in black.

And what's interesting is that if you then correlate the

extent to which visibility was reduced in the patients with

the location of their brain lesion, you can get a

map like this.

So this is known as lesion lesions into mapping.

This is a map of the lesions that were most

correlated with the drop in consciousness threshold.

And here you get a evidence for a contribution of

damage to the prefrontal cortex, to the anterior prefrontal cortex,

to the threshold for conscious awareness.

There's one other compound that we need to think carefully

about here, and that's not just performance, but I mentioned

a while ago that you can find cases where people

are performing better in one case rather than the other

due to unconscious information, but their confidence level is not

different.

Now, the problem is that in a typical Moscow experiment,

when people say that they saw a stimulus, then they're

often more confident on those trials than when they say

they didn't see a stimulus.

And you can see that here.

This is actually some data from our lab when subjects

say they saw a massive stimulus.

And they're more confident on the y axis compared to

when they said that they didn't see a massive it.

So the problem is that all these existing findings in

the literature on the front surprise activation being related to

conscious awareness might be consistent with these brain areas, coding

for the visibility or your awareness of the stimulus.

But it could also be consistent with these brain regions

being involved in representing confidence in your decisions.

So to look at this.

This was work done by my pastry student, Martha mazur,

and post-doc Nadine Easter.

And what we did is apply a machine learning decoding

procedure across the whole brain to try and deep code

people's allowance of the stimulus where they said they saw

it or not, and also what the identity of that

stimulus was.

So we can decode the identity of the stimulus, whether

it was tilted to the left or the right in

early visual areas.

And we can then decode their awareness in front of

proximal cortex.

So that's consistent with the picture of global ignition when

people say they saw it.

You get more activation, more decoding of awareness in response

across the network.

But when we then control for confidence in this analysis,

when we artificially match the distributions of confidence on yes

and no trials when they said they were aware of

it or not, and a lot of this activation actually

disappeared.

So after DOWNSAMPLING to ensure confidence was matched on these

trials, there was no longer any visibility, decoding, any awareness,

decoding in large swathes of the pre-frontal cortex.

Now, it was possible to still decode awareness from some

subregions of of all time, such as the posterior medial

frontal cortex.

So I think this is a very recent study, and

we just presented this a conference over the summer and

published it a few weeks ago.

And so I think we're still figuring out how to

interpret this.

So there's I think there's two implications of this work.

So the first is that this is a big issue.

This is a big deal that these are two distinct

phenomena.

On the one hand, we have confidence formation, monitoring, metacognition,

thinking about whether you got an answer right or wrong.

And this has been confounding all the studies of awareness

in the literature.

And so we could need to control for that to

isolate a pure awareness signal.

And this has been this view has been supported by

people like Standard Hand who think that monitoring self awareness

of whether you get things right or wrong should be

considered as distinct to global broadcast.

The alternative view is one that I favour is that

there are shared computational substrates for both monitoring and wireless.

Essentially what we mean by that is the ability to

be aware of how things are being processed and that

includes being confident in a response that you get.

The very feasibility confidence can be defined in terms of

being confident in a first order representation.

So that means there might actually be shared mechanisms that

underpin both confidence and awareness, and therefore it's unsurprising that

much of the classical correlates of consciousness disappear when we

control for confidence, because that's what we should expect under

that view.

So this is an ongoing debate and it's not been

resolved.

Yes.

And so what I've described is that we now have

a number of empirical signatures of consciousness.

We also have a number of theories.

And I just want to tell you one thing about

what's happening at the moment and in, I guess, conscious

to science as a ongoing project.

So one thing that people are a bit worried about

is that.

These theories are somewhat siloed.

They're being tested by different labs that don't often talk

to each other.

And there was actually a really interesting study from Italy,

Iran and the moderates group in Israel that they collected

all these different papers on consciousness in the literature together.

And then what they did is they mined the text

of those papers and asked which theory is being tested

in those papers.

And slightly concerningly in papers that said that they were

testing recurrent processing theory.

They would often report evidence for activation in the visual

cortex in support of consciousness, whereas in papers that said

they were testing global workspace theory, they would often report

activations in the front sprouts of network consciousness.

This is a bit of a concern, right?

Because it can't be that they're both right.

So there seems to be quite a bit of bias

between some labs focussed on one area, some labs focussed

on another theory.

And I think that there are now ongoing, really interesting

ongoing initiatives such as adversarial collaborations that have tried to

stop this happening and try and get labs who are

favouring different theories to actually work together and test competing

predictions.

I also think there might be a deeper problem here

in consciousness science, and that is the fact that actually

the theories of consciousness are not really thinking about what

the functions of consciousness are.

So in this recent article I suggested that there is

a consciousness, a solutions in need of problems.

People are putting forward theories of how consciousness might work

in the brain, but they're not necessary thinking about why

consciousness exists in the first place, and that is at

odds with other fields of psychology, right?

So if you have a theory of memory, for instance,

then you want to know what that memory is being

useful.

How is it helping the organism survive?

And instead, in conscious decisions, we often rely, I think,

a bit too much on intuition about the kind of

experience we're trying to explain.

Just as I introduced in a stop, I started the

lecture by saying, Imagine you are on a bridge in

London and looking at something sunset.

That's very intuitive, but it's not really constrained functionally.

And this lack of functional constraints is a problem because

the test of a good theory in psychology or neuroscience

is whether it can explain how a system performs a

particular function, how a theory of vision explains how we

categorise objects, or how a theory of memory explains how

we remember and forget.

All right.

So I think we can take a lot from the

next levels of analysis from David Marr.

So this is the idea that if you're trying to

explain, for instance, how a bird flies, you first need

to know something about why it's trying to flap its

wings.

What is the goal of flights is to take off

and leave the ground.

And that then constrains your search for the algorithm that

does that job.

Maybe you're going to take off and leave the ground

with jet engines and fixed wings.

Or maybe you're going to take off and leave the

ground with flapping your wings.

And then you can think about how that might be

implemented at the physical level.

And people have suggested that in neuroscience and psychology, it's

useful to think about all these levels of analysis.

So both the levels of implementation, such as how it

works at the level of brain areas in seconds and

algorithms, so computation, but also and this thing, this is

the level that often gets missed out.

What's the goal of the hour?

Why is it there in the first place?

And one thing I think is useful to constrain theories

of consciousness is the notion that consciousness, at the very

least, seems to be for sharing information.

And this has been put forward by Chris Pratt, who

used to be.

He's emeritus professor at UCL.

And he writes, The conscious experience is the one outcome

of the brain's information processing that can be shared with

others.

I think it's very hard to disagree.

This is essentially the definition of what we mean by

conscious experience.

When I'm a stimulus and you don't see it and

you can't tell me what it was, that's the definition

of it.

There may be lots of things that are influencing our

behaviour unconsciously.

I can't tell you what they are.

If I could, I would be conscious of them.

The consciousness is at the very least for sharing.

And what's interesting is that this kind of idea is

floated around the literature, but being somewhat obscure for many

years now.

So this is a book chapter written by the famous

neuroscientist Horace Barlow.

And and it's not as widely known as Chris's work

because it appeared in this book chapter in 1997.

But he writes here, I think, things that are very

similar.

So what makes the pursuit of communal goals possible as

humans is our ability to communicate with each other, which

is surely the direct and obvious result of being conscious.

Because if we weren't conscious of what we're thinking about

and feeling, we couldn't share that with others.

On the current hypothesis conscious experience gives one communicating one's

own experience to others.

That is its purpose and survival value.

So what we're what we've been working on recently is

trying to drill down into the algorithms that might support

sharing of conscious information.

So first of all, it's useful to think about what

is being shared.

And at the least, I think we can think of

both content.

So I might share with you the fact that I'm

feeling a bit tired or hungry, or I can see

a bird over there or, you know, that nice content

of words.

I also might share with you the vividness of that

experience.

I might say to you, I just can't continue this

lecture because my headache is so strong.

That's a very strong experience dominating my conscious experience.

And these things are interchangeable, right?

So I might be vividly aware of having a headache

or dully aware of it.

Partially.

Well.

And this in philosophy is known as the idea of

mental strength.

It goes all the way back to David HUME.

Recently, this paper from George Moralez, who has suggested that

the idea that mental strength is a phenomenal magnitude is

the strength of vividness, of an experience.

And it said by all conscious experience and explains that

degree of intensity.

And indeed, it seems that this is capturing something deep

about what it means to be aware of different types

of mental content.

Because when you put people in an experiment where they

actually have to share information to succeed, they naturally fall

back on this sharing of mental strength.

So this is an experiment from Barbara Graham's group where

they asked people to sit and look at two different

computer screens.

They have a different visual task to do.

The task is not so important at the moment.

But the important thing is that they would then allow

us just chat to each other and come up with

a joint decision about what they saw on the screen

and the kind of words they used.

This was done in Denmark, but the translations there are

things like, you know, I, I, I see see this

very well, but these I didn't see anything will go

with yours because I saw nothing.

I took a guess, a wild guess so that communicating

degrees of experience, strengths of experience.

And by doing so, they can then achieve a better

performance together than the best individual could alone.

Okay.

I just want to give you a flavour of this

model.

This is the part that I said was, uh.

That could be, could be sketches.

This is very much ongoing work, and it's not the

kind of thing you would necessarily be expected to talk

about in an exam, for instance.

But the idea that we're working with in our lab

is that we can start building in a this this

notion of awareness of mental strength into a generative model

of perceptual content that we can simulate in the computer,

and then we can devise hypotheses that test this awareness

related computation against its implementation in the brain.

So the idea behind generative models, this is very broad,

and you might have heard this idea in vision science

is the idea that what the brain is doing is

essentially building a generative model of the incoming sensory data.

So it's trying to infer the best guess of what

it's seeing based on the incoming prediction errors and the

sending predictions.

So this is known as predictive coding theory, predictive processing,

and more generally it's known as the theory of generative

models.

But what's interesting about this architecture is that awareness of

the degree of phenomenal magnitude or awareness of content is

not in that a lot of this stuff is suggested

to be proceeding completely unconsciously.

That's why we're not aware of how that percept of

an animal is being formed, how what's called an unconscious

inference.

We just unconsciously infer that an apple is there in

front of us.

And so we might need to start thinking about how

we can extend out these models to include additional higher

order levels that monitor the extent to which the system

thinks there is content in its first order generative model.

So this is a higher order theory of consciousness.

And the idea here is that awareness states are abstractions

about the presence or absence of perceptual content, and that

might support communication of mental strength.

And I will now just skip over the experiment because

I wanted to go to the part on on the

ethics.

But you have the slides and if anyone has any

particular questions about this and feel free to to come

and talk to me afterwards.

As I said, this is very much ongoing work that's

not published yet.

And so what we're trying to do with this work

is reverse the arrow here.

So we have functional constraints on what awareness is for

and that we hope we're very much at the start

of this project will start to enable us to, rather

than just remain siloed, testing different favourite theories that are

built often on intuition, to actually develop a working model

of the minimal types of computation that might allow the

communication of mental strength, the communication of degrees of experience,

and then test that against behaviour and brain activity.

Okay.

So just to derive some interim conclusions.

So we've looked at how techniques such as visual masking

and binocular rivalry allow the precise manipulation of awareness to

simple stimuli.

Conversion evidence for unconscious processing of stimuli is provided by

people performing above chance on indirect measures of information processing,

such as priming or forced choice responding.

The Neural correlates Consciousness research program identifies awareness with front

surprise selectivity and recurrent processing.

But note that it's important whenever you are reading this

literature to assess whether there whether the research is a

much different potential composition of performance and confidence when assessing

the basis of awareness.

And finally, I am excited by the idea of adopting

a more functional perspective, just like we do in other

fields of psychology.

So what is consciousness for might and allow us to

build a conversation among the consciousness related processing.

Okay.

So mainly we've talked about this difference in conscious content.

We talked briefly about difference in conscious level at the

start.

But now I just want to turn to the problems

that arise when we're able to start detecting conscious level

independence of what clinicians call vigilance.

So people who are in a vegetative state or some

forms of advanced dementia that are non-responsive might actually be

vigilant in the sense that they're awake, their eyes are

open.

But they may have very little.

In a consciousness.

At least that's what a lot of ICU doctors think

about people who are in a vegetative state.

And.

What's fascinating and somewhat disturbing is that there are cases

where, while clinically is usually described as condition, is wakefulness.

Without awareness, a subset of patients may show no reliable

behavioural signs and yet be able to communicate known as

a minimally conscious state.

And this is famously described by Jean-Dominique OB, who is

a former editor.

Elle and then became locked in in a minimally conscious

state and went on to write this beautiful book, The

Diving Bell and the Butterfly, just by fluttering his eyelid

to indicate what words he wanted on the page.

A whole book that.

And the problem is that recovery from this vegetative state

after around one year is very rare and often involves

severe disability.

So it raises ethical issues because you might read in

the media sometimes about decisions, controversial decisions to be made

by the legal and medical professions, about whether it's right

to remove life support from someone who's in a vegetative

state.

That's actually how this is not living anymore.

Now, obviously, this changes a lot.

If science can come along and say, actually, maybe there

is some in a conscious experience there and maybe it's

a meaningful one.

And a real advance came in this area from work

done by Adrian Owens Love, who's now in Canada.

And he showed that in some vegetative state patients, when

you put them into a functional MRI scanner and you

ask them to imagine either walking around the house or

playing tennis, then the activations you got in, say, the

motor cortex and the networks such as the prior to

cortex involved in spatial navigation were very similar to those

you got in controls.

Being asked to imagine walking around the house, all things

tennis.

So that was taken as some evidence that the patients,

even though they're behaviourally unresponsive, may well be conscious to

the same degree as the controls.

Similarly, it's been possible to use non-invasive transcranial magnetic stimulation

to ping the brain and then look at how distributed

responses reverberate around the brain using EEG.

I won't go into all the details of this, but

essentially what you can do is then take these recordings,

compress it down and ask how complex is the activation

that is elicited?

This is known as the Participation complexity index PCI.

And when you plot this perturbation to index on the

y axis here as a sorted according to the different

patient groups, then healthy subjects are up here.

So you see complex brain responses and patients who are

confirmed vegetative state down here.

But what's interesting is these behaviourally unresponsive MCI patients sometimes

drift over into the healthy range and even some vegetative

state patients might start to be providing some evidence of

consciousness.

So I just want to end with a single case

study.

So this was reported in this paper made you know,

in reviewing a lot of this literature in 2013.

So this was a 26 year old male who'd had

a motor vehicle accident, was admitted to hospital in a

coma.

And over the next 12 years remaining consistent behaviour defined

vegetative state.

And in February 2012, he used I wouldn't use this

tiny house method to answer multiple externally verifiable questions so

you could ask the subject to imagine playing tennis.

Yes.

Or imagine play walking around your house for no.

And then he was able to answer using that non-invasive

brain imaging method his own what his name was, the

name of his support worker and so on.

These are things that.

You know, only he could have known and were able

to be verified by the medics.

And then what becomes very difficult is the same technique

could then be used to ask non verifiable questions that

might be important for quality of care, which is what

he wants to watch on TV and whether he is

in pain.

So there's clear ethical implications here.

I won't read all these out, but just to highlight

what sorry, just to highlight a couple of things.

So first of all, we might have an intuition that

that must be a terrible quality of life being locked

in.

All you could do is imagine and create brain activity

patterns that you can't do anything.

You're sitting there just completely stationary.

But our intuitions about this might actually be wrong.

When you measure quality of life in patients who in

locked in syndrome patients, the majority say they're happy with

their quality of life even though they're locked in and

this is covered in the baby book.

And so the advantage of then single patient communication is

that a subset of those patients might not be happy,

but there might be very simple things that we can

do to change and be able to communicate with them.

Noninvasively is potentially very important.

Okay.

So just to conclude, so I've said a few of

these, and the last point here is that neuro imaging

may facilitate communication with behaviourally non-responsive patients and allow classification

of peaceful levels of awareness, but this raises deep ethical

issues.

Thanks very much.